-
In this compact, wonderfully iconoclastic book, Michael
Bryson sets himself two overlapping goals. First, he proffers a new interpretation
of Milton’s God alongside a re-interpretation of the Son’s role in both
Paradise Lost and Paradise Regained. Bryson contends that
the benign view of Milton’s God popular among Miltonists is entirely mistaken.
Milton’s God is disturbing, as Bryson states at numerous points throughout
this book, because he is meant to be disturbing, and the Son provides
an explicit alternative for the proper means of ruling. The second goal
is to critique the present state of Milton studies, which has the unfortunate
habit of conflating the literary character of “God” in Paradise Lost
with the actual deity worshipped in Christian churches and transforming
literary criticism into a form of prayer. “Milton studies,” Bryson
acerbically notes, “have often threatened to turn into Milton ministries”
(23; all emphases are in the original unless stated otherwise). This book’s
project could not be more ambitious, for Bryson seeks to not only change
our view of Milton’s poetry, but to challenge a deeply entrenched critical
paradigm. While I have occasional differences with his argument (duly noted
below), there can be no doubt that Bryson succeeds admirably in his project,
and The Tyranny of Heaven needs to become required reading for all
subsequent scholarship on Paradise Lost.
-
Unlike many books, in which the chapters form discrete
units, Bryson constructs The Tyranny of Heaven as an organic whole,
each chapter building on the previous one. The first, “Of Miltons and Gods,”
sets out the parameters for the upcoming chapters. Bryson proposes that
“The Father is not Milton’s illustration of how God is, but Milton’s
scathing critique of how, all too often, God is imagined (12). Therefore,
Milton “writes to re-imagine God” (12). In other words, Milton critiques
the all-too-common tendency among his contemporaries of imagining God as
a king: “To imagine God as a king was, for Milton, to imagine God as if
he were the Devil” (11). This thesis leads Bryson to the second aim
of this chapter: the critique of the Milton establishment, which usually
conflates the real with the literary God. The God of Paradise Lost,
Bryson reminds us, “is a poetic and a personal character,” but the refusal
to observe this fundamental distinction leads many, if not most, Miltonists
to conflate, as C. S. Lewis does in A Preface to “Paradise Lost”,
“Milton, Augustine, and the entire Christian church” (21). The result has
been unfortunate in two ways. First, as Bryson puts it, “the difference
between literary study and religious devotion becomes disconcertingly hard
to detect” (23). The second is a criticism that is breathtakingly overt
in its demarcation of legitimate and illegitimate forms of inquiry, as evidenced
by Lewis’s blunt announcement, quoted by Bryson, that the purpose of his
argument is to “prevent the reader from ever raising certain questions”
(21). While Lewis published those words in 1942, they continue to guide
Milton criticism, and as Bryson puts it, with equally remarkable candor:
“The time has come to say ‘enough’” (25).
-
Bryson begins his dismantling of this critical edifice
and his reconstruction of Milton into a much less orthodox figure in chapter
2, which has the rather bulky title, “’His Tyranny who Reigns’: The Biblical
Roots of Divine Kingship and Milton’s Rejection of ‘Heav’n’s King’” in Prose
and Poetry.” Bryson starts by noting some of the strategies Miltonists have
used to get around the uncomfortable fact Milton’s God looks and acts a
lot like the way Milton described another tyrant, Charles I. Joan Bennett,
for example, simply denies the parallel, and in another example of the coercive
nature of too much Milton criticism, she declares “that those who find such
a parallel are not to be taken seriously” (43). Another critic takes the
somewhat unlikely approach of arguing that it is okay for God to be an absolute
monarch, but not earthly monarchs (44). Bryson will have none of this. “Milton’s
poetic God is an impossibly powerful tyrannical figure,” and Milton
depicts the God of Paradise Lost (as opposed to the real God) in
this fashion “to express his contempt” for imagining God as a king (45).
To prove this point, Bryson scours Milton’s earlier writings on politics,
and finds not one positive reference to kingship. As Milton argues in A
Defence of the People of England, kingship originates from the Fall,
and kings issue “not from blessings but from curses [and] maledictions cast
upon fallen mankind” (63). Furthermore, “the Father in Paradise Lost
fits the definition of a tyrant” set out in Milton’s prose works (65).
For example, “The Father is first referred to as a ‘supreme king’ . . .
at I.735, after the demonic associations of kingship have been thoroughly
rehearsed over the last three hundred lines” (65).
-
The corollary to Bryson’s assertion that Milton’s God
“troubles precisely because he is supposed to trouble” (64) is his view
of Satan, who “seems heroic because he is heroic” (83). It would
seem that Bryson is tearing down the image of God in Milton’s epic only
to build up Satan, God’s antagonist, but that is, in fact, not entirely
the case, as Bryson argues in the third chapter, “’Who durst defy th’Omnipotent
to Arms’” Satan’s Fall from Hero to King.” Unlike most Miltonists, who assume
that Satan is evil from the poem’s start, Bryson’s point is that Satan does
not start off as the arch-villain and the Father of Lies: “Satan’s moral
advantage is that he does not begin as a tyrant.” (82) Satan begins the
poem, Bryson argues, as admirable, a figure who “more closely resembles
a character from Greek drama or Homeric epic than one from the Bible” (80).
And Milton carefully gives Satan a motive for rebellion “that is both credible
and forceful: the Father’s raising of the Son in Book 5” (92). The problem
with God’s decree, Bryson continues “is its belligerent tone: the Father
seems to be daring any and all to object” (93). Consequently, “Milton’s
Father deliberately creates hostility where none had previously existed
. . .” (94). Satan takes up the challenge, and borrowing rhetoric from Protestant
resistance theory, he rebels and takes about a third of the angels with
him. Satan’s problem, therefore, does not lie in his rebellion, but what
happens to him afterward: “Satan becomes a tyrant because in establishing
his infernal monarchy, he appeals to the very system of power that he once
rejected” (109). Once more, kingship corrupts. Satan “rejects the Son as
king, only to aspire to be a king himself—aspiring to be like God in the
wrong way” (111). In other words, Satan’s problem is not that he is God’s
opposite, but his acolyte.
-
If neither Satan nor God provide viable models, then who
does? Bryson answers this question in the fourth chapter, “That far be from
thee’: Divine Evil, Justification, and the Evolution of the Son from Warrior-King
to Hero.” The Son, Bryson proposes, "adopts an end more radical than
Satan’s (and closer to Milton’s) while employing means hitherto unseen in
Milton’s Heaven: he fights—through reason, self-sacrifice, and self-denial—to
overturn heavenly kingship, to refuse thrones both earthly and heavenly,
and to abolish kingship itself by reclaiming a Miltonic, internal definition
of glory, heroism, and true government" (115). To prove this point,
Bryson backtracks to continue with his analysis of Milton’s God as a hugely
negative figure, pointing out that when Milton famously states that his
purpose is to “justify the ways of God to men,” “justification” in the seventeenth
century did not mean “bear witness to the justice of,” as to use Ricks’
gloss, but to “explain the injustice of” (119). As Richard Baxter put it
in 1649, “Justification implyeth accusation” (quoted in Bryson, 120). Milton,
Bryson continues, “accuses God in the image of the Father so that
he may then acquit God in the image of the Son” (130). Thus, Bryson
traces the Son’s evolution from a warrior in Book 5 to a new kind of hero
in Book 3 (which chronologically comes later than the events of Book 5).
He has grown “weary of the use of force,” and he takes up “the persuasive
arms of his creator, the words, phrases, and arguments of Milton himself”
(139). Faced with the Father’s implacable demand for a death, any death,
the Son presents himself as a sacrifice, and “through his willingness
to die, [he] delivers the harshest and most devastating critique of the
Father that has yet been made” (142).
-
This argument reaches its logical conclusion in the fifth
and final chapter, “’Tempt not the Lord thy God’: The End of Kingship and
the Awareness of Divine Similitude in Paradise Regained.” This poem
constitutes “a final dismantling of divine kingship and rule. Anti-reign,
-glory, and –power, Paradise Regained is Milton’s ultimate rejection
of the image of God as king” (156). The Son, as Bryon argues, rejects all
forms of power, all forms of rule, and it is deeply important that the poem
does not end with the Son’s public ministry, but with his retiring to “his
mother’s house private” at the end of the poem (159). In so doing, "The
Son closes the door on the model of reign by force, the model of divinity
that pictures God as a king and leader of troops, and steps irrevocably
through the door that leads to a model of reign as inner accord with truth".
(170).
-
Overall, I found Bryson’s argument completely convincing.
His diagnosis of the present state of Milton is depressingly accurate, and
his twin analyses of the terrible nature of God in Paradise Lost
and Milton’s proposing the Son as an alternative model of rule is powerful,
accurate, and eloquent. There are also many riches in the details of this
book. I particularly learned from Bryson’s pointing out that in his early
translation of Psalm 2 “I, saith hee, /Anointed have my King (though ye
rebel),” Milton seems fully aware that the raising of a king will create
rebellion, since the phrase, “though ye rebel,” “appears nowhere in the
original Hebrew” (92). In 1653, Milton thus sketches in miniature the plot
of Paradise Lost. Bryson’s evident mastery of Hebrew lends his analysis
even more authority, and his decision to read Paradise Regained as
building on Paradise Lost enriches both poems.
-
Yet I also have some reservations. First, throughout
this book, Bryson repeatedly separates the actual from the literary God,
emphasizing that Milton is writing poetry, i.e., fiction, not theology,
and therefore one cannot and should not assume that the God of
Paradise
Lost is “intended to be synonymous with whatever ‘presence’ or ‘absence’
is pointed to with the word ‘God’” (116). At one level, of course, this
approach makes sense. Facts are not fiction, and fiction cannot be made
to substitute for facts. Yet I am not sure that this distinction was as
accepted in the early modern period as it is today. Consider, for instance,
Elizabeth I’s observation to the historian, William Lambarde, “I am Richard
II. Know ye not that?”
[1] Also, I am not
sure that Bryson himself entirely buys this proposition, given his difficulties
with maintaining the barrier between the image of God and God Himself. When
he writes, “Rather than reconciling Man to God, Milton is reconciling God
to Man” (120), it is not at all clear if by “God” Bryson means the deity
or a fictional representation of the deity. But most importantly, by positing
an unbridgeable wall separating the literary from the actual God, Bryson
runs the risk of draining the poem of its force. By depicting a God who
lies, who acts like a tyrant, who is “no less syntactically self-obsessed
than Satan is at any point in the poem” (140), Milton is not critiquing
“
images of God” (116), but
God. That is why so many critics
from Alexander Pope onward are so uncomfortable with Milton’s God, and why
they have spent so much time and energy proving that Milton’s God is not
what the poem manifestly says he is. Asserting that Milton wants to criticize
how his contemporaries imagine God, but not God Himself, means domesticating
the radically questioning nature of
Paradise Lost. Bryson’s revisionism
only takes us halfway, as the next step is to see how Milton puts God, not
an image of God, on trial.
[2]
-
Also, Samson Agonistes, the companion poem to
Paradise Regained (Milton published them together in 1671), is strangely
missing from this book. The absence is important, because in many ways,
Samson puts into question much of what Bryson says about Paradise
Regained, just as in Milton’s earlier companion poems, “Il Penseroso”
puts into question much of “L’Allegro.” If at “the end of Paradise
Regained, obedience is reasoned, internal, and given to
oneself” (169), then what happens when one’s inner promptings tell
one to commit mass murder? And if divinity is internalized, then how does
one know that it is God, and not Satan, or even one’s own madness, speaking?
While I am entirely convinced by Bryson’s analysis of the Son’s retreat
to his “mother’s house private” (does the presence of the mother in this
line constitutes yet another implicit criticism of the Father?), I wonder
if the events in Samson Agonistes qualify that retreat by suggesting
that the world will find you, regardless? Is, in other words, the quietism
at the end of Paradise Regained implicitly made impossible by the
treachery of Dalilah and active malevolence of God’s enemies? Finally, does
God’s reduced presence in Paradise Regained and unbroken silence
in Samson collectively portray a divine retreat from this world,
leaving us with a literally God-less void?
-
The Tyranny of Heaven is marvelous, sharply argued,
learned, and elegantly written. But even more, Michael Bryson has written
a necessary book, one that attempts to overthrow the rather stultifying
critical orthodoxy that presently governs Milton studies. I hope this book
gets the audience it so richly deserves.