Seneca's Essays Volume
III
Source: Lucius Annasus Seneca. Moral Essays. Translated
by John W. Basore. The Loeb Classical Library. London: W. Heinemann,1928-1935.
3 vols.: Volume III. Before using any portion of this text in any theme,
essay, research paper, thesis, or dissertation, please read the disclaimer.
Transcription conventions: Page numbers in Angle brackets refer
to the edition cited as the source. The Latin text, which appears on even-numbered
pages, is not included here. Words or phrases singled out for indexing
are marked by plus signs. In the index, numbers in parentheses indicate
how many times the item appears. A slash followed by a small letter or
a number indicates a footnote at the bottom of the page. Only notes of
historical, philosophical, or literary interest to a general reader have
been included. I have allowed Greek passages to stand as the scanner read
them, in unintelligible strings of characters.
Table of Contents: De Beneficiis
Index: Aeneid+(1)
| Akumal+(1) Antonio+(1)
| Antony+(2) |
Bassanio+(2) | benefits+(1) |
Best_of_all_possible+(1) | boast+(1)
|
motives_list+(1) |
business+(1) | Castiglione+(1)
| charisma+(1) |
Civic_Duty+(1) | common_bond+(2)
| Common_Humanity+(1) |
common_property+(1) | Coriolanus?+(1)
| Divine_Right+(1) |
duty+(2) | Epicureans+(1) |
Essay_on_Man_I+(1) | evil_as_good+(1)
| faith+(1) | flattery+(1)
| fool+(1) |
Foresight+(1) | forgive+(1) |
freedom+(1) | Freedom+(2) |
Friend+(1) | Gift+(1) |
GIFT+(1) | gift_as_link+(1)
| Gift_spirit+(1) |
gifts+(1) | give_freely+(1)
| given+(1) |
giving_motive+(1) | onourable+(1)
| God+(1) | goodwill+(1)
| Granville+(1) |
Graces+(1) |
gratia+(1) |
gratum+(1) | great_soul+(1)
| haero_stick+(1) |
Hal+(1) |
honestum+(2) |
hopes+(1) | Hotspur+(1) |
Iago+(2) | integrum+(1) |
judge_not+(2) | Kent+(3) |
law+(1) | Lear+(2) |
Lear_disgust+(1) | Lear_whole_plot+(1)
| magnitudo_animi+(1) |
memorem+(1) | Nature+(2) |
no_strings+(1) | nobody's_perfect+(1)
| Ode_to_Duty+(1) |
Paris+(1) | PlainDealer+(1)
| Plutarch's_Fortune+(1) |
Polonius+(1) | poor_is_rich+(1)
| Pope+(1) | promise+(2)
| promises+(1) |
Prospero+(1) | Reason+(1) |
Satan+(1) | Shylock+(3) |
simplicem+(1) |
social_animal+(1)
| social_glue+(1) |
Stoicism_basic+(1) | Swift+(1) |
Timon+(3)
| 11trustee+(1) |
virtue_in_peasants+(1) | Wdswth+(1)
| Wordsworth+(2) |
Wyf_of_Bath+(3) |
UCIUS ANNAEUS SENECA TO AEBUTIUS LIBERALIS
ON BENEFITS
BOOK I
AMONG the many and diverse errors of those who live reckless and thoughtless
lives, almost nothing that I can mention, excellent Liberalis, is more
disgraceful than the fact that we do not know how either to give or to
receive benefits. For it follows that, if they are ill placed, they
are ill acknowledged, and, when we complain of their not being returned,
it is too late for they were lost at the time they were given. Nor
is it surprising that among all our many and great vices, none is so common
as ingratitude. This I observe results from several causes.
The first is, that we do not pick out those
who are worthy of receiving our gifts. Yet when we are about to open
an account with anyone, we are careful to inquire into the means and manner
of life of our debtor; we do not sow seed in worn-out and unproductive
soil; but our benefits we give, or rather throw, away without any discrimination.
Nor would it be easy to say whether it is
more shameful to repudiate a benefit, or to ask the repayment of it; for
from the nature of such a trust, we
<Ess3-3>
ON BENEFITS, I. 1. 3-8
have a right to receive back only what is voluntarily returned.
To plead bankruptcy is, surely, most disgraceful, just for the reason that,
in order to perform the promised payment, what is needed is, not wealth,
but the desire; for, if a benefit is acknowledged, it is returned.
But, while those who do not even profess to be grateful are blameworthy,
so also are we. Many men we find ungrateful, but more we make so, because
at one time we are harsh in our reproaches and demands, at another, are
fickle and repent of our gift as soon as we have made it, at another, are
fault - finding and misrepresent the importance of trifles. Thus
we destroy all sense of gratitude, not only after we have given our benefits,
but even while we are in the act of giving them. Who of us has been
content to have a request made lightly, or but once? Who, when he
suspected that something was being sought from him, has not knit his brows,
turned away his face, pretended to be busy, by long-drawn conversation,
which he purposely kept from ending, deprived another of the opportunity
of making a request, and by various tricks baffled his pressing needs?
Who, when actually caught in a corner, has not either deferred the favor,
that is, been too cowardly to refuse it, or promised it with ungraciousness,
with frowning brows, and with grudging words that were scarcely audible?
Yet no one is glad to be indebted for what he had, not received, but extorted.
Can anyone be grateful to another for a benefit that has been haughtily
flung to him, or thrust at him in anger, or given out of sheer weariness
in order to save further trouble? Whoever expects that a man whom he has
wearied by delay and tortured by hope will feel any indebtedness
<Ess3-5>
ON BENEFITS, I. i. 8-10
deceives himself. A benefit is acknowledged in the same spirit
in which it is bestowed, and for that reason it ought not to be bestowed
carelessly; for a man thanks only himself for what he receives from an
unwitting giver. Nor should it be given tardily, since, seeing that in
every service the willingness of the giver counts for much, he who acts
tardily has for a long time been unwilling. And, above all, it should
not be given insultingly; for, since human nature is so constituted that
injuries sink deeper than kindnesses, and that, while the latter pass quickly
from the mind, the former are kept persistently in memory, what can he
expect who, while doing a favor, offers an affront? If you pardon
such a man for giving a benefit, you show gratitude enough, There is no
reason, however, why the multitude of ingrates should make us more reluctant
to be generous. For, in the first place, as I have said, we ourselves
increase their number; and, in the second place, not even the mortal gods
are deterred from showing lavish and unceasing kindness to those who are
sacrilegious and indifferent to them. For they follow their own nature,
and in their universal bounty {great_soul+}
include even those who are ill interpreters of their gifts. Let us
follow these as our guides in so far as human weakness permits; let us
make our benefits, not investments, but gifts+.
The man who, when he gives, has any thought of repayment deserves to be
deceived. But suppose it has turned out ill. Both children
and wives have disappointed our hopes, yet we marry and rear children,
and so persistent are we in the face of experience that, after being conquered,
we go back to war and, after being shipwrecked, we go back to sea.
How much more fitting
<Ess3-7>
ON BENEFITS, I.
to persevere in bestowing benefits! For if a man stops giving
them because they were not returned, his purpose in giving them was to
have them returned, and he supplies a just excuse to the in ingrate, whose
disgrace lies in not making a return, it is permissible. {GIFT+}
How many are unworthy of seeing the light! Yet the day dawns.
How many complain because they have been born! Yet Nature begets
new progeny, and even those who would rather not have been, she suffers
to be. To seek, not the fruit of benefits, but the mere doing of
them, and to search for a good man even after the discovery of bad men
- this is the mark of a soul that is truly great and good. What glory
would there be in doing good to many if none ever deceived you? But
as it is, it is a virtue to give benefits that have no surety of being
returned, whose fruit is at once enjoyed by the noble mind. So true
is it that we ought not to allow such a consideration to rout us from our
purpose and make us less prone to do a very beautiful thing, that, even
were I deprived of the hope of finding a grateful man, I should prefer
not recovering benefits to not giving them, because he who does not give
them merely forestalls the fault of the ungrateful man. I will explain
what I mean. He who does not return a benefit, sins more, he who
does not give one, sins earlier.
To shower bounties on the mob should you delight, xxx
Full many must you lose, for one you place aright./a
In the first verse two points are open to criticism for, on the one hand,
benefits ought not to be showered upon the mob, and, on the other, it is
not right to be wasteful of any thing, least of all of benefits; for, if
you eliminate discernment in giving them, they cease
<Ess3-9>
ON BENEFITS, I.
to be benefits, and will fall under any other name you please.
The sentiment of the second is admirable, for it allows a solitary benefit
that is well placed to compensate for the loss of many that have been wasted.
But consider, I beg of you, whether it may not be truer doctrine and more
in accord with the generous spirit of the benefactor to urge him to give
even though not one of his benefits is likely to be well placed.
For "many must you lose" is a false sentiment; not one is lost, because
a loser is one who had kept an account. In benefits the book- keeping
is simple - so much is paid out; if anything comes back, it is gain, if
nothing comes back, there is no loss. I made the gift for the sake
of giving. No one enters his benefactions in his account-book, or
like a greedy tax-collector calls for payment upon a set day, at a set
hour. The good man never thinks of them unless he is reminded of
them by having them returned; otherwise, they transform themselves into
a loan. To regard a benefit as an amount advanced is putting it out
at shameful interest. No matter what the issue of former benefits
has been, still persist in conferring them upon others; this will be better
even if they fall unheeded into the hands of the ungrateful, for it may
be that either shame or opportunity or example will some day make these
grateful. Do not falter, finish your task, and complete the role of the
good man. Help one man with money, another with credit, another with influence,
another with advice, another with sound precepts. Even wild beasts
are sensible of good offices, and no creature is so savage that it will
not be softened by kindness and made to love the hand that gives it.
The lion will let a keeper handle his mouth with impunity,
<Ess3-11>
ON BENEFITS, I. ii. 5-iii. 4
the elephant, for all his fierceness, is reduced to the docility of
a slave by food; so true is it that even creatures whose condition excludes
the comprehension and appraisement of a benefit, are nevertheless won over
by persistent and steadfast kindness. Is a man ungrateful for one
benefit? Perhaps he will not be so for a second. Has he forgotten
two benefits? Perhaps a third will recall to memory the others also that
have dropped from his mind. That man will waste his benefits who
is quick to believe that he has wasted them; but he who presses on, and
heaps new benefits upon the old, draws forth gratitude even from a heart
that is hard and unmindful. In the presence of multiplied benefits
the ingrate will not dare to lift his eyes; wherever he turns, fleeing
his memory of them, there let him see you - encircle him with your benefits.
Of the nature and property of these I shall
speak later if you will permit me first to digress upon questions that
are foreign to the subject - why the Graces+/a {gratia+}
are three in number and why they are sisters, why they have their hands
interlocked, and why they are smiling and youthful and virginal, and are
clad in loose and transparent garb. Some would have it appear that
there is one for bestowing a benefit, another for receiving it, and a third
for returning it; others hold that there are three classes of benefactors
- those who earn benefits,/b those who return them, those who receive and
return them at the same time. But of the two explanations do you
accept as true whichever you like; yet what profit is there in such knowledge?
Why do the sisters hand in hand dance in a ring which returns upon itself?
For the reason that a benefit passing
<Ess3-13>
ON BENEFITS, I. iii 4-7
in its course from hand to hand returns nevertheless to the giver; the
beauty of the whole is destroyed if the course is anywhere broken, and
it has most beauty if it is continuous and maintains an uninterrupted succession.{gift_as_link+}
In the dance, nevertheless, an older sister has especial honour, as do
those who earn benefits. Their faces are cheerful, as are ordinarily
the faces of those who bestow or receive benefits. They are young
because the memory of benefits ought not to grow old. They are maidens
because benefits are pure and undefiled and holy in the eyes of all; and
it is fitting that there should be nothing to bind or restrict them, and
so the maidens wear flowing robes, and these, too, are transparent because
benefits desire to be seen.
There may be someone who follows the Greeks
so slavishly as to say that considerations of this sort are necessary;
but surely no one will believe; also that the names which Hesiod assigned
to the Graces have any bearing upon the subject. He called the eldest
Aglaia, the next younger Euphrosyne, the third Thalia. Each one twists
the significance of these names to suit himself, and tries to make them
fit some theory although Hesiod simply bestowed on the maidens the name
that suited his fancy. And so Homer changed the name of one of them,
calling her Pasithea, and promised her in marriage in order that it might
be dear that, if they were maidens, they were not Vestals./a I could find
another poet in whose writings they are girdled and appear in robes of
thick texture or of Phryxian wool./b And the reason that Mercury stands
with them is, not that argument or eloquence commends benefits, but simply
that the painter chose to picture them so.
<Ess3-15>
ON BENEFITS, I. iii. 8-iv. 1
Chrysippus, too, whose famous acumen
is so keen and pierces to the very core of truth, who speaks in order to
accomplish results, and uses no more words than are necessary to make himself
intelligible - he fills the whole of his book with these puerilities, insomuch
that he has very little to say about the duty itself of giving, receiving,
and returning a benefit; and his fictions are not grafted upon his teachings,
but his teachings upon his fictions. For, not to mention what Hecaton
copies from him, Chrysippus says that the three Graces are daughters of
Jupiter and Eurynome, also that, while they are younger than the Hours,
they are somewhat more beautiful, and therefore have been assigned as companions
to Venus. In his opinion, too, the name of their mother has some
significance, for he says that she was called Eurynome/a <daughter of Ocean,
"wide spreading"> because the distribution of benefits is the mark of an
extensive fortune; just as if a mother usually received her name after
her daughters, or as if the names that poets bestow were genuine!
As a nomenclator lets audacity supply the place of memory, and every time
that he is unable to call anyone by his true name, he invents one, so poets
do not think that it is of any importance to speak the truth, but, either
forced by necessity or beguiled by beauty. They impose upon each
person the name that works neatly into the verse. Nor is it counted
against them if they introduce a new name into the list; for the next poet
orders the maidens to take the name that he devises. And to prove
to you that this is so, observe that Thalia, with whom we are especially
concerned, appears in Hesiod as Charis,/b {charisma+}
in Homer as a Muse.
But for fear that I shall be guilty of the
fault that
<Ess3-17>
ON BENEFITS, I. iv. 1-5
I am criticizing, I shall abandon all these questions, which are so
remote that they do not even touch the subject. Only do you defend
me if anyone shall blame me for having put Chrysippus in his place - a
great man, no doubt, but yet a Greek, one whose acumen is so finely pointed
that it gets blunted and often folds back upon itself; even when it seems
to be accomplishing something, it does not pierce, but only pricks.
But what has acumen to do here? What we need is a discussion of benefits
and the rules for a practice that constitutes the chief bond of human society;{Granville+}
we need to be given a law of conduct in order that we may not be inclined
to the thoughtless indulgence that masquerades as generosity, in order,
too, that this very vigilance, while it tempers, may not check our liberality,
of which there ought to be neither any lack nor any excess; we need to
be taught to give willingly, to receive willingly, to return willingly,
and to set before us the high aim of striving, not merely to equal, but
to surpass in deed and spirit those who have placed us under obligation,
for he who has a debt of gratitude to pay never catches up with the favor
unless he outstrips it; the one should be taught to make no record of the
amount, the other to feel indebted for more than the amount. To this most
honourable rivalry in outdoing benefits by benefits Chrysippus urges us
by saying that, in view of the fact that the Graces are the daughters of
Jupiter, we should fear that by showing a lack of gratitude we might become
guilty of sacrilege and do an injustice to such beautiful maidens! But
teach thou me the secret of becoming more beneficent and more grateful
to those who do me a service, the secret of the rivalry that is born in
the hearts of the obligers
<Ess3-19>
ON BENEFITS, I. iv. 5-v. 3
and the obliged so that those who have bestowed forget, those who owe
persistently remember. As for those absurdities, let them be left
to the poets, whose purpose it is to charm the car and to weave a pleasing
tale. But those who wish to heal the human soul, to maintain faith in the
dealings of men, and to engrave upon their minds the memory of services
let these speak with earnestness and plead with all their power; unless,
perchance, you think that by light talk and fables and old wives' reasonings
it is possible to prevent a most disastrous thing - the abolishment of
benefits.
But, just as I am forced to touch lightly
upon irrelevant questions, so I must now explain that the first thing we
have to learn is what it is that we owe when a benefit has been received.
For one man says that he owes the money which he has received, another
the consulship, another the priesthood, another the administration of a
province. But these things are the marks of services rendered, not
the services themselves. A benefit cannot possibly be touched by
the hand; its province is the mind. There is a great difference between
the matter of a benefit and the benefit itself; and so it is neither gold
nor silver nor any of the gifts which are held to be most valuable that
constitutes a benefit, but merely the goodwill+
of him who bestows it. But the ignorant regard only that which meets
the eye, that which passes from hand to hand and is laid hold of, while
they attach little value to that which is really rare and precious.
The gifts that we take in our hands, that we gaze upon, that in our covetousness
we cling to, are perishable; for fortune or injustice may take them from
us. But a benefit endures even after that through which it
<Ess3-21>
ON BENEFITS, I. v. 3-vi. 2
was manifested has been lost; for it is a virtuous act, and no power
can undo it.
If I have rescued a friend from pirates, and
afterwards a different enemy seized him and shut him up in prison, he has
been robbed, not of my benefit, but of the enjoyment of my benefit.
If I have saved a man's children from shipwreck or a fire and restored
them to him, and afterwards they were snatched from him either by sickness
or some injustice of fortune, yet, even when they are no more, the benefit
that was manifested in their persons endures. All those things, therefore,
which falsely assume the name of benefits, are but the services through
which the goodwill of a friend reveals itself. The same thing is
true also of other bestowals - the form of the bestowal is one thing, the
bestowal itself another. The general presents a soldier with a breast-chain
or with a mural and civic crown. But what value has the crown in
itself? What the purple-bordered robe? What the fasces?
What the tribunal and the chariot? No one of these things is an honour,
they are the badges of honour. In like manner that which falls beneath
the eye is not a benefit - it is but the trace and mark of a benefit.
What then is a benefit? It is the act
of a wellwisher who bestows joy and derives joy from the bestowal of it,
and is inclined to do what he does from the prompting of his own will.
And so what counts is, not what is done or what is given, but the spirit
of the action, because a benefit consists, not in what is done or given,
but in the intention of the giver or doer. The great distinction
that exists between these things, moreover, may be grasped from the simple
statement that a benefit is un-
<Ess3-23>
ON BENEFITS, I. vi. 2-vii. 2
doubtedly a good, while what is done or given is neither a good nor
an evil. It is the intention that exalts small gifts, gives lustre
to those that are mean, and discredits those that are great and considered
of value; the things themselves that men desire have a neutral nature,
which is neither good nor evil/a; all depends upon the end toward which
these are directed by the Ruling Principle/b {God+}
that gives to things their form. The benefit itself is not something
that is counted out and handed over, just as, likewise, the honour that
is paid to the gods lies, not in the victims for sacrifice, though they
be fat and glitter with gold, but in the upright and holy desire of the
worshippers. Good men, therefore, are pleasing to the gods with an
offering of meal and gruel; the bad, on the other hand, do not escape impiety
although they dye the altars with streams of blood.
If benefits consisted, not in the very desire
to benefit, but in things, then the greater the gifts are which we have
received, the greater would be the benefits. But this is not true;
for sometimes we feel under greater obligations to one who has given small
gifts out of a great heart, who "by his spirit matched the wealth of kings,"/c
who bestowed his little, but gave it gladly, who beholding my poverty forgot
his own, who had, not merely the willingness, but a desire to help, who
counted a benefit given as a benefit received, who gave it with no thought
of having it returned, who, when it was returned, had no thought of having
given it, who not only sought, but seized, the opportunity of being useful.
On the other hand, as I have said before, those benefits win no thanks,
which, though they seem great
<Ess3-25>
ON BENEFITS, I. vii. 2-ix. 1
from their substance and show, are either forced from the giver or are
carelessly dropped, and that comes much more gratefully which is given
by a willing rather than by a full hand. The benefit which one man
bestowed upon me is small, but he was not able to give more; that which
another gave me is great, but he hesitated, he put it off, he grumbled
when he gave it, he gave it haughtily, he, published it abroad, and the
person he tried to please was not the one on whom he bestowed his gift
- he made an offering, not to me, but to his pride.
Once when many gifts were being presented
to Socrates by his pupils, each one bringing according to his means, Aeschines,
who was poor, said to him: "Nothing that I am able to give to you
do I find worthy of you, and only in this way do I discover that am a poor
man. And so I give to you the only thing that I possess - myself.
This gift, such as it is, I beg you to take in good part, and bear in mind
that the others, though they gave to you much, have left more for themselves."
"And how," said Socrates, "could it have been anything but a great gift
- unless maybe you set small value upon yourself? And so I shall
make it my care to return you to yourself a better man than when I received
you." By this present Aeschines surpassed Alcibiades, whose heart matched
his riches,/a and the wealthy youths with all their splendid gifts.
You see how even in pinching poverty the heart finds the means for generosity.
These, it seems to me, were the words of Aeschines: "You, O Fortune,
have accomplished nothing by wishing to make me poor; I shall none the
less find for this great man a
<Ess3-27>
ON BENEFITS, I. ix. 1-4
gift that is worthy of him, and, since I cannot give to him from your
store, I shall give from my own." Nor is there any reason for you to supposethat
he counted himself cheap: the value he set upon himself was himself.
And so clever a young man was he that he discovered a way of giving to
himself -Socrates! It is not the size of our respective benefits,
but the character of the one from whom they come that should be our concern.
a/A man is shrewd if he does not make himself
difficult of access to those who come with immoderate desires, and encourages
their wild expectations by his words although in reality he intends to
give them no help; but his reputation suffers if he is sharp of tongue,
stern in countenance, and arouses their jealousy by flaunting his own good
fortune. For they court, and yet loathe, the prosperous man, and
they hate him for doing the same things that they would do if they could.
They make a laughing-stock of other men's
wives, not even secretly, but openly, and then surrender their own wives
to others. If a man forbids his wife to appear in public in a sedan-chair
and to ride exposed on every side to the view of observers who everywhere
approach her, he is boorish and unmannerly and guilty of bad form, and
the married women count his demands detestable. If a man makes himself
conspicuous by not having a mistress, and does not supply an allowance
to another man's wife, the married women say that he is a poor sort and
is addicted to low pleasures and affairs with maidservants. The result
of this is that adultery has become the most seemly sort of betrothal,
and the bachelor is in accord with the widower, since
<Ess3-29>
ON BENEFITS, I. ix. 5-x. 2
the only man who takes a wife is one who takes away a wife. Now
men vie in squandering what they have stolen and then in regaining by fierce
and sharp greed what they have squandered; they have no scruples; they
esteem lightly the poverty of others and fear poverty for themselves more
than any other evil; they upset peace with their injustices, and hard press
the weaker with violence and fear. That the provinces are plundered,
that the judgement-seat is for sale, and, when two bids have been made,
is knocked down to one of the bidders is of course not surprising, since
it is the law of nations that you can sell what you have bought!
But, because the subject is alluring, my ardour
has carried me too far; and so let me close by showing that it is not our
generation only that is beset by this fault. The complaint our ancestors
made, the complaint we make, the complaint our posterity will make, is
that morality is overturned, that wickedness holds sway, and that human
affairs and every sin are tending toward the worse. Yet these things
remain and will continue to remain in the same position, with only a slight
movement now in this direction, now in that, like that of the waves, which
a rising tide carries far inland, and a receding tide restrains within
the limits of the shoreline. Now adultery will be more common than
other sins, and chastity will tear off its reins; now a furore for feasting
and the most shameful scourge that assails fortunes, the kitchen, will
prevail, and now excessive adornment of the body and the concern for its
beauty that displays an unbeauteous mind; now ill-controlled liberty will
burst forth into wantonness and presumption; and now the progress will
be toward
<Ess3-31>
ON BENEFITS, I. x. 2-5
cruelty, on the part both of the state and of the individual, and to
the insanity of civil war, which desecrates all that is holy and sacred;
sometimes it will be drunkenness on which honour is bestowed, and he who
can hold the most wine will be a hero.
Vices do not wait expectantly in just one
spot, but are always in movement and, being at variance with each other,
are in constant turmoil, they rout and in turn are routed; but the verdict
we are obliged to pronounce upon ourselves will always be the same: wicked
we are, wicked we have been, and, I regret to add, always shall be.
Homicides, tyrants, thieves, adulterers, robbers, sacrilegious men, and
traitors there always will be; but worse than all these is the crime of
ingratitude, unless it be that all these spring from ingratitude, without
which hardly any sin has grown to great size.
Do you beware of committing this crime as
being the greatest there is; if another commits it, pardon it as being
the most trivial. For the sum of your injury is this - you have wasted
a benefit. For you have the best part of it still unharmed - the
fact that you gave it. But, although we ought to be careful to confer
benefits by preference upon those who will be likely to respond with gratitude,
yet there are some that we shall do even if we expect from them poor results,
and we shall bestow benefits upon those who, we not only think will be,
but we know have been, ungrateful. For example, if I shall be able
to restore to someone his sons by rescuing them from great danger without
any risk to myself, I shall not hesitate to do so. If a man is a
worthy one, I shall defend him even at the cost of my own blood, and share
his peril; if he is unworthy, and I shall be able
<Ess3-33>
ON BENEFITS, I. x. 5-xi. 4
to rescue him from robbers by raising an outcry, I shall not be slow
to utter the cry that will save a human being.
I pass next to the discussion of what benefits
ought to be given and the manner of their bestowal. Let us give what
is necessary first, then what is useful, then what is pleasurable, particularly
things that will endure. But we should begin with necessities; for
that which supports life impresses the mind in one way, that which adorns
or equips life, in quite another. It is possible for a man to be
scornful in his estimate of a gift which he can easily do without, of which
he may say: "Take it back, I do not want it; I am content with what
I have." Sometimes it is a pleasure, not merely to give back, but to hurl
from you, what you have received.
Of the benefits that are necessary, some,
those without which we are not able to live, have the first place, others,
those without which we ought not to live, the second, and still others,
those without which we are not willing to live, the third. The first
are of this stamp - to be snatched from the hands of the enemy, from the
wrath of a tyrant, from proscription, and the other perils which in diverse
and uncertain forms beset human life. The greater and the more formidable
the danger from any one of these, the greater will be the gratitude that
we shall receive when we have banishes it; for the thought of the greatness
of the ills from which they have been freed will linger in men's minds,
and their earlier fear will enhance the value of our service. And
yet we ought not to be slower in saving a man than we might be, solely
in order that his fear may add weight to our service. Next to these
come the blessings without
<Ess3-35>
ON BENEFITS, I. xi. 4-6
which, indeed, we are able to live, yet death becomes preferable, such
as liberty and chastity and a good conscience. After these will be
the objects that we hold dear by reason of kinship and blood and experience
and long habit, such as children, wives, household gods, and all the other
things to which the mind becomes so attached that to be robbed of them
seems to it more serious than to be robbed of life.
Next in order are the useful benefits, the
matter of which is wide and varied; here will be money, not in excess,
but enough to provide for a reasonable standard of living; here will be
public office and advancement for those who are striving for the higher
positions, for nothing is more useful than to be made useful to oneself.
All benefits beyond these come as superfluities
and tend to pamper a man. In the case of these, our aim shall he
to make them acceptable by reason of their timeliness, to keep them from
being commonplace, and to give the sort of things that either few or few
in our own time or in this fashion, have possessed, the sort of things
that, even if they are not intrinsically valuable, may become valuable
by reason of the time and place. Let us consider what will be likely
to give the greatest pleasure after it has been bestowed, what is likely
to meet the eyes of the owner ov.y case we shall be careful not to send
gifts that are superfluous, for example, the arms of the chase to a woman
or to an old man, books to a bumpkin, or nets/a to one who is devoted to
study and letters. On, the other hand we shall be equally careful,
while wishing to
<Ess3-37>
ON BENEFITS, I. xi. 6-xii. 3
send what will be acceptable, not to send gifts that will reproach a
man with his weakness, as for example wines to a drunkard and medicines
to a valetudinarian. For a gift that recognizes a vice of the recipient
tends to be, not a boon, but a bane.
If the choice of what is to be given is in
our own hands, we shall seek especially for things that will last, in order
that our gift may be as imperishable as possible. For they are few
indeed who are so grateful that they think of what they have received even
if they do not see it. Yet even the ungrateful have their memory
aroused when they encounter the gift itself, when it is actually before
their eyes and does not let them forget it, but instead brings up the thought
of its giver and impresses it upon their mind. And let us all the
more seek to make gifts that will endure because we ought never to remind
anyone of them; let the object itself revive the memory that is fading.
I shall be more willing to give wrought than coined silver; more willing
to give statues than clothing or something that will wear out after brief
usage. Few there are whose gratitude survives longer than the object
given; there are more who keep gifts in mind only so long as they are in
use. For my part, if it is possible, I do not want my gift to perish;
let it survive, let it cling fast to my friend, let it live with him.
No one is so stupid as to need the warning
that he should not send gladiators or wild beasts to a man who has just
given a public spectacle, or send a present of summer clothing in midwinter
and winter clothing in midsummer. Common sense should be used in
bestowing a benefit; there must be regard
<Ess3-39>
ON BENEFITS, I. xii. 3-xiii. 2
for time, place, and the person, for some gifts are acceptable or unacceptable
according to circumstances. How much more welcome the gift will be
if we give something that a man does not have, rather than something with
which he is abundantly supplied, something that he has long searched for
and has not yet found, rather than something which he is likely to see
everywhere! Presents should be, not so much costly, as rare and choice
- the sort which even a rich man will make a place for; just as the common
fruits, of which we shall grow tired after a few days, give us pleasure
if they have ripened out of season. And, too, people will not fail
to appreciate the gifts which either no one else has given to them, or
which we have given to no one else.
When Alexander of Macedonia, being victorious
over the East, was puffed up with more than human pride, the Corinthians
sent their congratulations by an embassy, and bestowed upon him the right
of citizenship in their state. This sort of courtesy made Alexander
smile, whereupon one of the ambassadors said to him: "To no one besides
Hercules and yourself have we ever given the right of citizenship." Alexander
gladly accepted so marked an honour, and bestowed hospitality and other
courtesy upon the ambassadors, reflecting, not who they were who had given
him the privilege of citizenship, but to whom they had given it; and, slave
as he was to glory, {Hotspur+} of which
he knew neither the true nature nor the limitations, following the footsteps
of Hercules and of Bacchus, and not even halting his course where they
ceased, he turned his eyes from the givers of the honour to his partner
in it, just as if heaven, to which in supreme vanity he aspired, were now
his because
<Ess3-41>
ON BENEFITS, I. xiii. 3-xiv. 2
he was put on a level with Hercules! Yet what resemblance to him
had that mad youth who instead of virtue showed fortunate/a {Plutarch's_Fortune+}
rashness? Hercules conquered nothing for himself; he traversed the
world, not in coveting, but in deciding what to conquer, a foe of the wicked,
a defender of the good, a peacemaker on land and sea. But this other
was from his boyhood a robber and a plunderer of nations, a scourge alike
to his friends and to his foes, one who found his highest happiness in
terrorizing all mortals, forgetting that it is not merely the fiercest
creatures, but also the most cowardly, that are feared on account of their
deadly venom. {Iago+}
But let me return now to my subject.
Whoever gives a benefit to anyone you please, gives acceptably to no one;
in an inn or a hotel no one regards himself as the guest of the landlord,
or at a public feast as the intimate friend of the man who is giving it,
for one may well say: "What favor, pray, has he conferred upon me?
The same, to be sure, that he has conferred onhat other fellow, whom he
scarcely knows, and on that one over there, who is his enemy and a most
disreputable man. Did he consider that I was worthy of it?
He merely indulged a personal weakness/b!" If you want to give what will
be acceptable, make the gift a rare one - anyone can endure being indebted
for that! Let no one gather from my words that I desire to restrain
liberality, to bridle it in with tighter reins; let it indeed go forth
as far as it likes, but let it go by a path, and not wander. It is
possible to distribute bounty in such a way that each person, even if he
has received his gift in company with others, will
<Ess3-43>
ON BENEFITS, I. xiv. 3-xv. 2
think that he is simply one of a
crowd. Let everyone have some mark of intimacy which permits
him to hope that he has been admitted to greater favor than
others. He may say: "I received the same thing that
So-and-so did, but without asking for it. I received the same
thing that So-and-so did, but at the end of a short time, whereas he
had long since earned it. There are those who have the same thing,
but it was not given to them with the same words, with the same,
friendliness, on the part of the bestower. So-and-so received his
gift after he had asked for it; I did not ask for mine.
So-and-so received a gift, but he could easily make return, but his
old age and his irresponsible childlessness/a afforded great
expectation, to me more was given although the same thing was given,
because it was given without expectation of any return." A courtesan
will distribute her favours among her many lovers in such a way that
each one of them will get some sign of her intimate regard; just so
the man who wishes his benefactions to be appreciated should
contrive both to place many under obligation, and yet to see that
each one of them gets something that will make him think he is
preferred above all the others. In truth, I place no
obstacles in the way of benefits; the more there are and the greater
they are, the more honour will they have. But let judgement be
used; for what is given in a haphazard and thoughtless manner will
be prized by no one. Wherefore, if anyone supposes that in
laying down these rules we mean to narrow the bounds of liberality,
and to open to it a less extensive field, he really has heard my
admonitions incorrectly. For what virtue do we <Ess3-45>
ON BENEFITS, I. xv, 2-6
Stoics venerate more? What virtue do
we try more to encourage? Who are so fitted to give such
admonition as ourselves - we who would establish the fellowship of
the whole human race? What, then, is the case? Since no
effort of the mind is praiseworthy even if it springs from right
desire, unless moderation turns it into some virtue, I protest
against the squandering of liberality. The benefit that it is
a delight to have received, yea, with outstretched hands, is the one
that reason delivers to those who are worthy, not the one that
chance and irrational impulse carry no matter where - one that it is
a pleasure to display and to claim as one's own. Do you give the
name of benefits to the gifts whose author you are ashamed to
admit? But how much more acceptable are benefits, how much
deeper do they sink into the mind, never to leave it, when the
pleasure of them comes from thinking, not so much of what has been
received, as of him from whom it was received! Crispus Passienus used
often to say that from some men he would rather have their esteem
than their bounty, and that from others he would rather have their
bounty than their esteem; and he would add examples. "In the
case of the deified Augustus," he would say, "I prefer his esteem,
in the case of Claudius, his bounty." I, for my part, think that we
should never seek a benefit from a man whose esteem is not
valued. What, then, is the case? Should not the gift
that was offered by Claudius have been accepted? It should,
but as it would have been accepted from Fortune, who you were well
aware might the next moment become unkind. And why do we
differentiate the two cases that thus have <Ess3-47>
ON BENEFITS, I. xv. 6
merged? A gift is not a benefit if the
best part of it is lacking - the fact that it was given as a mark of
esteem. Moreover the gift of a huge sum of money, if neither
reason nor rightness of choice has prompted it, is no more a benefit
than is a treasure trove. There are many gifts that ought to
be accepted, and yet impose no obligation.
<Ess3-49>
BOOK II
Now let us examine, most excellent
Liberalis, what still remains from the first part of the subject -
the question of the way in which a benefit should be given.
And in this matter I think that I can point out a very easy course -
let us give in the manner that would have been acceptable if we were
receiving. Above all let us give willingly, promptly, and
without hesitation. No gratitude is felt for a, benefit when
it has lingered long {haero_stick+}
in the hands of him who gives it, or when the giver has seemed sorry
to let it go, and has given it with the air of one who was robbing
himself. Even though some delay should intervene, let us avoid
in every way the appearance of having deliberately delayed;
hesitation is the next thing to refusing, and gains no
gratitude. For, since in the case of a benefit the chief
pleasure of it comes from the intention of the bestower, he who by
his very hesitation has shown that he made his bestowal unwillingly
has not "given," but has failed to withstand the effort to extract
it; there are many indeed who become generous only from a lack of
courage. The benefits that stir most gratitude are those which
are readily and easily obtainable and rush to our hands, where, if
there is any delay, it has come only from the delicacy of the <Ess3-51>
ON BENEFITS, II. 1. 3-ii. 2
recipient. The best course is to
anticipate each one's desire; the next best, to indulge it.
The first is the better - to forestall the request before it is put;
for, since a respectable man seals his lips and is covered with
blushes if he has to beg, he who spares him this torture multiplies
the value of his gift. The man who receives a benefit because
he asked for it, does not get it for nothing, since in truth, as our
forefathers, those most venerable men, discerned, no other thing
costs so dear as the one that entreaty buys. If men had to
make their vows to the gods openly, they would be more sparing of
them; so true is it that even to the gods, to whom we most rightly
make supplication, we would rather pray in silence and in the
secrecy of our hearts. xxxIt is unpleasant and burdensome to have to
say, "I ask," and as a man utters the words he is forced to lower
his eyes. {Bassanio+} A friend and every
one whom you hope to make a friend by doing him a service must be
excused from saying them; though a man gives promptly, his benefit
has been given too late if it has been given upon request.
Therefore we ought to divine each man's desire, and, when we have
discovered it, he ought to be freed from the grievous necessity of
making a request; the benefit that takes the initiative, you may be
sure, will be one that is agreeable and destined to live in the
heart. If we are not so fortunate as to anticipate the asker,
let us cut him off from using many words; {Antonio+} in
order that we may appear to have been, not asked, but merely
informed, let us promise at once and prove by our very haste that we
were about to act even before we were solicited. Just as in
the case of the sick suitability of food aids recovery, and plain
water given at the <Ess3-53>
ON BENEFITS, II. ii. 2-iii. 3
right time serves as a remedy, so a benefit,
no matter how trivial and commonplace it may be, if it has been,
given promptly, if not an hour has been wasted, gains much in value
and wins more gratitude than a gift that, though costly, has been
laggard and long considered. One who acts thus readily leaves
no doubt that he acts willingly; and so he acts gladly, and his face
is clothed with the joy he feels. Some who bestow
immense benefits spoil them by their silence or reluctant words,
which give the impression of austerity and sternness, and, though
they promise a gift, have the air of refusing it. How much
better to add kindly words to kindly actions, and grace the gifts
you bestow with humane and generous speech! In order that the
recipient may reproach himself because he was slow to ask, you might
add the familiar rebuke I am angry with you because, when you needed
something, you were not willing to let me know long ago, because you
took so much pains in putting your request, because you invited a
witness to the transaction. Truly I congratulate myself because you
were moved to put my friendliness to the test; next time you will
demand by your own right whatever need - this once I pardon your
bashfulness. The result of this will be that he will value
your friendliness more than your gift, no matter what it was that he
had come to seek. The bestower attains the highest degree of
merit, the highest degree of generosity, only when it will be
possible for the man who has left him to say: "Great is the
gain that I have made today; but I would rather have found the giver
to be the sort of man he was than to have had many times the amount
that <Ess3-55>
ON BENEFITS, II. iii. 3-v. i
we were talking about come to me in some
other way; for the spirit he has shown I can never return enough
gratitude. Yet
there are very many who by the harshness of their words and by their
arrogance make their benefits hateful, so that, after being
subjected to such language and such disdain, we regret that we have
obtained them. And then, after the matter has been promised, a
series of delays ensues; but nothing is more painful than when you
have to beg even for what you have been promised. Benefits
should be bestowed on the spot, but there are some from whom it is
more difficult to get them than to get the promise of them.
You have to beg one man to act as a reminder, another to finish the
transaction; so a single gift is worn down by passing through many
men s hands, and as a result very little gratitude is left for the
giver of the promise, for every later person whose help must be
asked reduces the sum due to him. And so, if you wish the
benefactions that you bestow to be rewarded with gratitude, you will
be concerned to have them come undiminished to those to whom they
were promised, to have them come entire and, as the saying is,
"without deduction." Let no one intercept them, let no one retard
them; for in the case of a benefit that you are going to give, no
one can appropriate gratitude to himself without reducing what is
due to you.
Nothing is so bitter as long suspense; some can endure more calmly
to have their expectation cut off than deferred. Yet very many are
led into this fault of postponing promised benefits by a perverted
ambition to keep the crowd of their petitioners from becoming
smaller; such are the tools of royal power, <Ess3-57>
ON BENEFITS, II. V. 1-4
who delight in prolonging a display of
arrogance, and deem themselves to be robbed of power unless they
show long and often, to one after another, how, much power they
have. They do nothing promptly, nothing once for all; their
injuries are swift, their benefits slow. And therefore the
words of the comic poet, you are to believe, are absolutely true,
Know you not this - the
more delay you make, The less of
gratitude from me you take?/a And so a man cries out in
an outburst of noble anger: "If you are going to do anything,
do it;" and: "Nothing is worth such a price; I would rather
have you say no at once." When the mind has been, reduced to a state
of weariness, and, while waiting for a benefit, begins loathe it,
can one possibly feel grateful for it? Just as the sharpest
cruelty is that which prolongs punishment, and there is a sort of
mercy in killing swiftly because the supreme torture brings with it
its own end, whereas the worst part of the execution that is sure to
come is the interval that precedes it, so, in the case of a gift,
gratitude for it will be the greater, the less long it has hung in
the balance. For it is disquieting to have to wait even for
blessings, and, since most benefits afford relief from some trouble,
if a man leaves another to long torture when he might release him at
once, or to tardy rejoicing, he has done violence to the benefit he
confers. All generosity moves swiftly. and he who acts willingly is
prone to act quickly; if a man gives help tardily, deferring it from
day to day, he has not given it heartily. Thus he has lost two
valuable things - time and the proof of his friendly intent; tardy
goodwill smacks of ill-will. <Ess3-59>
ON BENEFITS, II. vi. 1-vii. 2 In every
transaction, Liberalis, not the least important part is the manner
in which things are either said or done. Much is gained by
swiftness, much is lost by delay. Just as, in the case of
javelins, while all may have the same weight of iron, it makes an
infinite difference whether they are hurled with a swing of the arm,
or slip from a slackened hand, and just as the same sword will both
scratch and deeply wound - the tightness of the grasp which directs
it makes the difference - so, while the thing that is given may be
just the same, the manner of the giving is all important. How
sweet, how precious is a gift, for which the giver will not suffer
us to pay even our thanks, which he forgot that he had given even
while he was giving it! For to reprimand a man at the very
moment that you are bestowing something upon him is madness, it is
grafting insult upon an act of kindness. Benefits, therefore,
must not be made irritating, they must not be accompanied by
anything that is unpleasant, even if there should be something upon
which you would like to offer advice, choose a different time. Fabius Verrucosus used
to say that a benefit rudely given by a hard-hearted man is like a
loaf of gritty bread, which a starving man needs must accept, but
which is bitter to eat. When Marius Nepos, a
praetorian, being in debt, asked Tiberius Caesar to come to his
rescue, Tiberius ordered him to supply him with the names of his
creditors; but this is really, not making a gift, but assembling
creditors. When the names had been supplied, he wrote to Nepos
that he had ordered the money to be paid, adding at the same time
some offensive admonition. The result was that Nepos had <Ess3-61>
ON BENEFITS, 11. vii. 2-ix. 2
neither a debt nor, a true benefit; Tiberius
freed him from his creditors, but failed to attach him to
himself. Yet Tiberius had his purpose; he wished to prevent
others, I suppose, from rushing to him in order to make the same
request. That, perhaps, may have been an effective way to
check, through a sense of shame, the extravagant desires of men, but
a wholly different method must be followed by one who is giving a
benefit. In order that what you give may become the more
acceptable, you should enhance its value by every. possible
means. Tiberius was really not giving a benefit - he was
finding fault. And - to say in passing what I think about this
other point - it is not quite proper even for a prince to bestow a
gift in order to humiliate. "Yet," it may be said, "Tiberius
was not able even in this way to escape what he was trying to avoid;
for after this a goodly number were found to make the same request,
and he ordered them all to explain to the senate why they were in
debt, and under this condition he granted to them specific sums."
But liberality that is not, it is censorship; I get succour, I get a
subsidy from the prince - that is no benefit which I am not able to
think of without a blush. It was a judge before whom I was
summoned; I had to plead a case in order to obtain my request.
And so all moralists are united upon the principle that it is
necessary to give certain benefits openly, others without witnesses
- openly, those that it is glorious to obtain, such as military
decorations or official honours and any other distinction that
becomes more attractive by reason of publicity; on the other hand,
those that do not give promotion or prestige, yet come to the rescue
of bodily infirmity, <Ess3-63>
ON BENEFITS, II. ix. 2-x. a
of poverty, of disgrace - these should be
given quietly, so that they will be known only to those who receive
the benefit.
Sometimes, too, the very man who is helped must even be deceived in
order that he may have assistance, and yet not know from whom he has
received it. There is a story that Arcesilaus had a friend
who, though he was poor, concealed his poverty; when, however, the
man fell ill and, being unwilling to reveal even this, lacked money
for the necessities of life, Arcesilaus decided that he must assist
him in secret; and so, without the other's knowledge, he slipped a
purse under his pillow in order that the fellow who was so uselessly
reserved might find, rather than receive, what he needed.
"What, then? - shall a man not know from whom he has received?" In
the first place, he must not know, if an element of the benefit is
just that fact; then, again, I shall do much else for him I shall
bestow upon him many gifts, and from these he may guess the author
of the first one; lastly, while he will not know that he has
received a gift, I shall know that I have given one. "That is
not enough," you say. That is not enough if you are thinking
of making an investment; but if a gift, you will give in the manner
that will bring most advantage to the recipient. You will be
content to have yourself your witness; otherwise your pleasure
comes, not from doing a favour, but from being seen to do a
favour. "I want the man at least to know!" Then it is a debtor
that you are looking for. " I want the man at least to know!"
What? if it is more to his advantage, more to his honour, more to
his pleasure not to know, will you not shift your position? "I
want him to know!" So, then, <Ess3-65>
ON BENEFITS, II. X. 4-xi. 2
you will not save a man's life in the
dark? I do not deny that, whenever circumstances permit, we
should have regard for the pleasure we get from the willingness of
the recipient; but, if he needs, and yet is ashamed, to be helped,
if what we bestow gives offence unless it is concealed - then I do
not put my good deed into the gazette/a! Of course I am
careful not to reveal to him that the gift came from me, since it is
a first and indispensable requirement, never to reproach a man with
a benefit, nay, even to remind him of it. For, in the case of
a benefit, this is a binding rule for the two who are concerned -
the one should straightway forget that it was given, the other
should never forget that it was received. Repeated reference to
our services wounds and crushes the spirit of the other. He
wants to cry out like the man who, after being saved from the
proscription of the triumvirs by one of Caesar's friends, because he
could not endure his benefactor's arrogance, cried "Give me back to
Caesar!" How long will you keep repeating: "It is I who saved
you, it is I who snatched you from death"? Your service, if I
remember it of my own will, is truly life; if I remember it at
yours, it is death. I owe nothing to you if you saved me in order
that you might have someone to exhibit. How long will you
parade me? How long will you refuse to let me forget my
misfortune? In a triumph, I should have had to march but once!
No mention should be made of what we have bestowed; to remind a man
of it is to ask him to return it. It must not be dwelt upon,
it must not be recalled to memory - the only way to remind a man of
an carlier gift is to give him another. <Ess3-67>
ON BENEFITS, II. xi. 2-5
And we must not tell others of it,
either. Let the giver of a benefit hold his tongue; let the
recipient talk. For the same thing that was said to another
man when he was boasting of a benefit he had conferred will be said
to you. "You will not deny," said the beneficiary, "that you
have had full return." "When?" inquired the other. "Many
times," was the reply, "and in many places -that is, every time and
in every where that you have told of it!" But what need is there to
speak of a benefit, what need to preempt the right that belongs to
another? There is someone else who can do more creditably what
you are doing, someone who in telling of your deed will laud even
your part in not telling of it. You must adjudge me ungrateful
if you suppose that no one will know of your deed if you yourself
are silent! But so far from its being permissible for us to
speak of it, even if anyone tells of our benefits in our presence,
it is our duty to reply: "While this man is in the highest
degree worthy to receive even greater benefits, yet I am more
conscious of being willing to bestow all possible benefits upon him
than of having actually bestowed them hitherto." And in saying even
this there must be no show of currying favour, nor of that air with
which some reject the compliments that they would rather
appropriate. Besides, we must add to generosity every possible
kindness. The farmer will lose all that he has sown if he ends his
labours with putting in the seed; it is only after much care that
crops are brought to their yield; nothing that is not encouraged by
constant cultivation from the first day to the last ever reaches the
stage of fruit. In the case of benefits the same rule
holds. Can there possibly be any greater <Ess3-69>
ON BENEFITS, II. xi. 5-xii. 2
benefits than those that a father bestows
upon his children? Yet they are all in vain if they are
discontinued in the child's infancy - unless longlasting devotion
nurses its first gift. And the same rule holds for all other
benefits - you will lose them unless you assist them; it is not
enough that they were given, they must be tended. If you wish
to have gratitude from those whom you lay under an obligation, you
must, not merely give, but love, your benefits. Above all, as
I have said, let us spare the ears; a reminder stirs annoyance, a
reproach hatred. In giving a benefit nothing ought to be
avoided so much as haughtiness. Why need your face show
disdain, your words assumption? The act itself exalts
you. Empty boasting must be banished; our deeds will speak
even if we are silent. The benefit that is haughtily bestowed
wins, not only ingratitude, but ill-will. Gaius Caesar granted
life to Pompeius Pennus, that is, if failure to take it away is
granting it; then, when Pompeius after his acquittal was expressing
his thanks, Caesar extended his left foot to be kissed. Those
who excuse the action, and say that it was not meant to be insolent,
declare that he wanted to display his gilded, - no, his golden -
slipper studded with pearls./a Yes, precisely - what insult to the
consular if he kissed gold and pearls, since otherwise he could have
found no spot on Caesar's person that would be less defiling to
kiss? But this creature, born for the express purpose of changing
the manners of a free state into a servitude like Persia's, thought
it was not enough if a senator, an old man, a man who had held the
highest public offices, bent the knee and prostrated himself before
brim in full sight of the <Ess3-71>
ON BENEFITS, II. xii. 2-xiii. 3
nobles, just as the conquered prostrate
themselves before their conquerors; he found a way of thrusting
Liberty down even lower than the knees! Is not this a
trampling upon the commonwealth, and too although the detail may not
seem to some of any importance - with the left foot? For he
would have made too little display of shameful and crazy insolence
in wearing slippers a when he was trying a consular for his life
unless he had thrust his imperial hobnails/b in the face of a
senator! O Pride,
the bane of great fortune and its highest folly! How glad we
are to receive nothing from thee! How thou dost turn every
sort of benefit into an injury! How will all thy acts become
thee! The higher thou hast lifted thyself, the lower thou dost
sink, and provest that thou hast no right to lay claim to those
blessings that cause thee to be so greatly puffed up; thou dost
spoil all that thou givest. And so I like to ask her why she is so
fond of swelling out her chest, of marring her expression and the
appearance of her face to the extent of actually preferring to wear
a mask instead of human visage. The gifts that please are
those that are bestowed by one who wears the countenance of a human
being, all gentle and kindly, by one who, though he was my superior
when he gave them, did not exalt himself above me, but, with all the
generosity in his power, descended to my own level, and banished all
display from his giving, who thus watched for the suitable moment
for the purpose of coming to my rescue with timely, rather than with
necessary, aid. The only way in which we shall ever convince
these arrogant creatures that they are ruining their benefits by
their insolence is to show them that benefits do not appear more
important <Ess3-73>
ON BENEFITS, II. xiii. 3-xiv. 3
simply because they were given with much
noise; and, too, that they themselves do not appear more important
in anyone's eyes because of that; that the importance of pride is an
illusion, and tends to cause hatred for actions that ought to be
loved. There are
certain gifts that are likely to harm those who obtain them, and, in
the case of these, the benefit consists, not in giving, but in
withholding, them; we shall therefore consider the advantage rather
than the desire of the petitioner. For we often crave things
that are harmful, and we are not able to discern how destructive
they are because our judgement is hampered by passion; but, when the
desire has subsided, when that frenzied impulse, which puts prudence
to rout, has passed, we loathe the givers of the evil gifts for the
destruction they have wrought. As we withhold cold water from
the sick, and the sword from those who are stricken with grief and
the rage of self- destruction, as we withhold from the insane
everything that they could use against themselves in a fit of
frenzy, so, in general, to those who petition for gifts that will be
harmful we shall persistently refuse them although they make earnest
and humble, sometimes even piteous, request. It is right to
keep in view, not merely the first effects, but the outcome, of our
benefits, and to give those that it is a pleasure, not merely to
receive, but to have received. For there are many who say, "I know
that this will not be to his advantage, but what can I do? He
begs for it, and I cannot resist his entreaties. It is his own look-
out - he will blame himself, not me." No, you are wrong - you are
the one he will blame, and rightly so. When he comes to his
right mind, when the frenzy that inflamed his soul has subsided, <Ess3-75>
ON BENEFITS, II. xiv. 3-xv. 1
how can he help hating the one who helped to
put him in the way of harm and danger? It is cruel kindness to
yield to requests that work the destruction of those who make
them. Just as it is a very noble act to save the life of a
man, even against his will and desire, so to lavish upon him what is
harmful, even though he begs for it, is but hatred cloaked by
courtesy and civility. Let the benefit that we give be one
that will become more and more satisfying by use, one that will
never change into an evil. I will not give a man money if I
know that it will be handed over to an adulteress, nor will I allow
myself to become a partner in dishonour, actual or planned; if I
can, I will restrain crime, if not, I will not aid it. Whether
a man is being driven by anger in a direction that he ought not to
take, or is being turned from the safe course by a burning ambition,
I shall not permit him to draw from me myself the power to work any
harm, nor allow it to be possible for him to act at any future
time: "That man has ruined me by his love." Often there is no
difference between the favours of our friends and the prayers of our
enemies; into the ills that the latter desire may befall us, the
former by their inopportune kindness drive us, and provide the
means. Yet, often as it happens, what can be more disgraceful
than that there should be no difference between benificence and
hatred? Let us never bestow benefits that can redound to our
shame. Since the sum total of friendship consists in putting a
friend on an equality with ourselves, consideration must be given at
the same time to the interests of both. I shall give to him if he is
in need, yet not to the extent of bringing need upon myself; I shall
come to his aid if he is at the point of ruin, yet <Ess3-77>
ON BENEFITS, II. xv. i-xvi. 1
not to the extent of bringing ruin upon my
self, unless by so doing I shall purchase the safety of a great man
or a great cause. I shall never give a benefit which I should
be ashamed to ask for. I shall neither magnify the value of a
small service, nor allow a great service to pass as a small one;
for, just as he who takes credit for what he gives destroys all
feeling of gratitude, so he who makes clear the value of what he
gives recommends his gift, does not make it a reproach. Each
one of us should consider his own means and resources in order that
we may not bestow either a larger or a smaller amount than we are
able to give. We should take into account, too, the character
of the person to whom we are giving; for some gifts are too small to
come fittingly from the hands of a great man, and some are too.
large for the other to take. Do you therefore compare the
characters of the two concerned, and over against these weigh the
gift itself in order to determine whether, in the case of the giver,
it will be either too onerous or too small, and whether, on the
other hand, the one who is going to receive it will either disdain
it or find it too large. Alexander - madman that he was, and
incapable of conceiving any plan that was not grandiose - once
presented somebody with a whole city. When the man to whom he
was presenting it had taken his own measure, and shrank from
incurring the jealousy that so great a gift would arouse,
Alexander's reply was: "I am concerned, not in what is
becoming for you to receive, but in what is becoming for me to
give." This seems a spirited and regal speech, but in reality it is
most stupid. No, nothing, in itself, makes a becoming gift for
any man; it all depends upon who gives it and who receives it - the
when, wherefore, <Ess3-79>
ON BENEFITS, II. xvi. 2-xvii. 2
and where of the gift, and all the other
items without which there can be no true reckoning of the value of
the deed. You puffed-up creature! If it is not becoming fox
the man to accept the gift, neither is it becoming for you to give
it; the relation of the two in point of character and rank is taken
into account, and, since virtue is everywhere a mean,/a excess and
defect are equally an error. Granted that you have such power,
and that Fortune has lifted you to such a height that you can fling
whole cities as largesses (but how much more magnanimous it would
have been not to take, than to squander, them!), yet it is possible
that there is someone who is too small to put a whole city in his
pocket! A certain
Cynic once asked Antigonus for a talent his reply was that this was
more than a Cynic had a right to ask for. After this rebuff
the cynic asked for a denarius; here the reply was that this was
less than a king could becomingly give. "Such sophistry," it
may be said, "is most unseemly; the king found a way of not giving
either. In the matter of the denarius he thought only of the king,
in the matter of the talent only of the Cynic, although he might
well have given the denarius on the score that the man was a Cynic,
or the talent on the score that he himself was a king. Grant
that there may be some gift that is too large for a Cynic to
receive, none is too small for a king to bestow with honour if it is
given out of kindness." If you ask my opinion, I think the king was
right; for the situation is intolerable that a man should ask for
money when he despises it. Your Cynic has a declared hatred of
money; he has published this sentiment, he has chosen this role -
now he must play it. It is most unfair for him to obtain money
while he <Ess3-81>
ON BENEFITS, II. xvii. 2-5) |
boasts of poverty. It is, then, every
man's duty to consider not less his own character than the character
of the man to whom he is planning to give assistance. I wish to make use of
an illustration that our Chrysippus once drew from the playing of
ball. If the ball falls to the ground, it is undoubtedly the
fault either of the thrower or the catcher; it maintains its course
only so long as it does not escape from the hands of the two players
by reason of their skill in catching and throwing it. The good
player, however, must of necessity use one method of hurling the
ball to a partner who is a long way off, and another to one who is
near at hand. The same condition applies to a benefit.
Unless this is suited to the character of both, the one who gives
and the one who receives, it will neither leave the hands of the
one, nor reach the hands of the other in the proper manner. If
we are playing with a practised and skilled partner, we shall be
bolder in throwing the ball, for no matter how it comes his ready
and quick hand will promptly drive it back; if with an unskilled
novice, we shall not throw it with so much tension and so much
violence, but play more gently, and run slowly forward guiding the
ball into his very hand. The same course must be followed in
the case of benefits; some men need to be taught, and we should show
that we are satisfied if they try, if they dare, if they are
willing. But we ourselves are most often the cause of
ingratitude in others, and we encourage them, to be ungrateful, just
as if our benefits could be great only when it was impossible to
return gratitude for them! It is as if some spiteful player
should purposely try to discomfit his fellow-player, to the
detriment of the game, of course, which can be carried on only in a
<Ess3-83>
ON BENEFITS, II. xvii. 6-xviii. 2
spirit of cooperation. {Gift_spirit+} There are many, too, who are
naturally so perverse that they would rather lose what they have
bestowed than appear to have had any return - arrogant, purse-proud
men. But how much better, how much more kindly would it be to
aim at having the recipients also do regularly their part, to
encourage a belief in the possibility of repaying with gratitude, to
put a kindly interpretation upon all that they do, to listen to
words of thanks as if they were an actual return, to show oneself
complaisant to the extent of wishing that the one upon whom the
obligation was laid should also be freed from it. A
money-lender usually gets a bad name if he is harsh in his demands,
likewise too, if he is reluctant to accept payment, and obstinately
seeks to defer it. But in the ease of a benefit it is as right
to accept a return as it is wrong to demand it. The best man is he
who gives readily, never demands any return, rejoices if a return is
made, who in all sincerity forgets what he has bestowed, and accepts
a return in the spirit of one accepting a benefit. Some men
are arrogant, not only in giving, but even in receiving, benefits, a
mistake which is never excusable. For let me now pass to the
other side of the subject in order to consider how men ought to
conduct themselves in accepting a benefit. Every obligation
that involves two people makes an equal demand upon both. When
you have considered the sort of person a father ought to be, you
will find that there remains the not less great task of discovering
the sort that a son should be; it is true that a husband has certain
duties, yet those of the wife are not less great. In the
exchange of <Ess3-85>
ON BENEFITS, II. xviii, 2-4
obligations each in turn renders to the
other the service that he requires, and they desire that the same
rule of action should apply to both, but this rule, as Hecaton says,
is a difficult matter; for it is always hard to attain to Virtue,
even to approach Virtue; for there must be, not merely achievement,
but achievement through reason. Along the whole path of life
Reason+ must be our guide, all our acts, from the smallest to
the greatest, must follow her counsel; as she prompts, so also must
we give. Now her
first precept will be that it is not necessary for us to receive
from everybody. From whom, then, shall we receive? To answer
you briefly, from those to whom we could have given. Let us
see, in fact, whether it does not require even greater discernment
to find a man to whom we ought to owe, than one on whom we ought to
bestow, a benefit. For, even though there should be no unfortunate
consequences (and there are very many of them), yet it is grievous
torture to he under obligation to someone whom you object to; on the
other hand, it is a very great pleasure to have received a benefit
from one whom you could love even after an injury, when his action
has shown a friendship that was in any case agreeable to be also
justified. Surely, an unassuming and honest man will be in a
most unhappy plight if it becomes his duty to love someone when it
gives him no pleasure. But I must remind you, again and again,
that I am not speaking of the ideal wise man to whom every duty is
also a pleasure, who rules over his own spirit, and imposes upon
himself any law that he pleases, and always observes any that he has
imposed, but of the man who with all his imperfections desires to
follow the perfect path, yet has passions <Ess3-87>
ON BENEFITS, II. xviii. 5-7
that often are reluctant to obey. And
so it is necessary for me to choose the person from whom I wish to
receive a benefit; and, in truth, I must be far more careful in
selecting my creditor for a benefit than a creditor for a
loan. For to the latter I shall have to return the same amount
that I have received, and, when I have returned it, I have paid all
my debt and am free; but to the other I must make an additional
payment, and, even after I have paid my debt of gratitude, the bond
between us still holds; for, just when I have finished paying it, I
am obliged to begin again, and friendship endures/a; and, as I would
not admit an unworthy man to my friendship, so neither would I admit
one who is unworthy to the most sacred privilege of benefits, from
which friendship springs. "But," you reply, "I am not always
permitted to say, 'I refuse'; sometimes I must accept a benefit even
against my wish. If the giver is a cruel and hot-tempered
tyrant, who will deem the spurning of his gift an affront, shall I
not accept it? Imagine in a like situation a brigand or a
pirate or a king with the temper of a brigand or a pirate.
What shall I do? Is such a man altogether unworthy of my being
indebted to him?" When I say that you must choose the person to whom
you would become indebted, I except the contingency of superior
force or of fear, for, when these are applied, all choice is
destroyed. But, if you are free, if it is for you to decide
whether you are willing or not, you will weigh the matter thoroughly
in your mind; if necessity removes any possibility of choice, you
will realize that it is for you, not to accept, but to obey.
No man contracts an obligation by accepting something that he had no
power to reject; if you wish to <Ess3-89>
ON BENEFITS, II, xviii. 7-xix. 2
discover whether I am willing, make it
possible for me to be unwilling. "Yet suppose it was life that he
gave you!" It makes no difference what the gift is if it is not
given willingly to one who accepts willingly; though you have saved
my life, you are not for that reason my saviour. Poison at times
serves as a remedy, but it is not for that reason counted as a
wholesome medicine. Some things are beneficial, and yet impose
no obligation. A man, who had approached a tyrant for the
purpose of killing him, lanced a tumour for him by the blow of his
sword; he did not, however, for that reason receive the thanks of
the tyrant, though by doing him injury he cured him of the disorder
to which the surgeons had not had the courage to apply the knife.
You see that the
act itself is of no great consequence, since it appears that the man
who from evil intent actually renders a service has not given a
benefit; for chance designs the benefit, the man designs
injury. We have seen in the amphitheatre a lion, who, having
recognized one of the beast- fighters as the man who had formerly
been his keeper, protected him from the attack of the other
beasts. Is, then, the assistance of the wild beast to be
counted a benefit? By no means, for it neither willed to do
one, nor actually did one with the purpose of doing it. In the
same category, in which I have placed the wild beast, do you place
your tyrant - the one as well as the other has given life, neither
the one or the other a benefit. For, since that which I am
forced to receive is not a benefit, that also which puts me under
obligation to someone against my will is not a benefit. You
ought to give me first the right to choose for myself, then the
benefit. <Ess3-91>
ON BENEFITS, II. xx. I-xxi. 1
It is an oft-debated question
whether Marcus Brutus ought to have received his life from the hands
of the deified Julius when in his opinion it was his duty to kill
him. The reason that led him to kill Caesar I shall discuss
elsewhere, for, although in other respects he was a great man in
this particular he seems to me to have acted very wrongly, and to
have failed to conduct himself in accordance with Stoic teaching.
Either he was frightened by the name of king, though a state reaches
its best condition under the rule of a just king, or he still hoped
that liberty could exist where the rewards both of supreme power and
of servitude were so great, or that the earlier constitution of the
state could be restored after the ancient manners had all been lost,
that equality of civil rights might still exist and laws maintain
their rightful place there where he had seen so many thousands of
men fighting to decided, not whether, but to which of the two
masters, they would be slaves! How forgetful, in truth, he
was, either of the law of nature or of the history of his own city,
in supposing that, after one man had been murdered, no other would
be found who would have the same aims - although a Tarquin had been
discovered after so many of the kings had been slain by the sword or
lightning! But Brutus ought to have received his life, yet
without regarding Caesar in the light of a father, for the good
reason that Caesar had gained the right to give a benefit by doing
violence to right; for he who has not killed has not given life, and
has given, not a benefit, but quarter. A question that offers
more opportunity for debate is what should be the course of a
captive if the price of his ransom is offered to him by a man who
prostitutes his body and dishonours his mouth. Shall I permit
a <Ess3-93>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxi. 1-5
filthy wretch to save me? Then, if I
have been saved, how shall I return my gratitude? Shall I live
with a lewd fellow? Shall I not live with my deliverer?
I shall tell you what in that case would be my course. Even
from such a man I shall receive the money that will buy my
freedom. I shall, however, receive it, not as a benefit, but
as a loan; then I shall repay the money to him, and, if I ever have
an opportunity to save him from a perilous situation, I shall save
him as for friendship, which is a bond between equals, I shall not
condescend to that, and I shall regard him, not as a preserver, but
as a banker, to whom I am well aware that I must return the amount
that I have received. It is possible that,
while a man may be a worthy person for me to receive a benefit from,
it will injure him to give it; this I shall not accept for the very
reason that he is ready to do me a service with inconvenience, or
even with risk, to himself. Suppose that he is willing to
defend me in a trial, but by his defence of me will make an enemy of
the king; I am his enemy if, since he is willing to run a risk for
my sake, I do not do the easier thing - run my risk without him. A foolish and silly
example of this is a case that Hecaton cites. Arcesilaus, he
says, refused to accept a sum of money that was offered to him by a
man who was not yet his own master a for fear that the giver might
offend his miserly father. But what was praiseworthy in his
act of refusing to come into possession of stolen property, of
preferring not to receive it than to restore it? For what
self-restraint is there in refusing to accept the gift of another
man's property? If
there is need of an example of a noble spirit, let <Ess3-95>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxi. 5-xxiii, i
us take the case of Julius Graccinus' a rare
soul, whom Gaius Caesar killed simply because he was a better man
than a tyrant found it profitable for anyone to be. This man,
when he was receiving contributions from his friends to meet the
expense of the public games, refused to accept a large sum of money
that Fabius Persicus had sent; and, when those who were thinking,
not of the senders, but of what was sent, reproached him because he
had rejected the contribution, he replied: "Am I to accept a
benefit from a man from whom I would not accept a toast to my
health?" And, when a consular named Rebilus, a man of an equally bad
reputation, had sent an even larger sum and insisted that he should
order it to be accepted, he replied: "I beg your pardon; but I
have already refused to accept money from Persicus." Is this
accepting a present or is it picking a senate? When we have decided
that we ought to accept, let us accept cheerfully, professing our
pleasure and letting the giver have proof of it in order that he may
reap instant reward; for, as it is a legitimate source of happiness
to see a friend happy, it is a more legitimate one to have made him
so. Let us show how grateful we are for the blessing that has
come to us by pouring forth our feelings, and let us bear witness to
them, not merely in the hearing of the giver, but everywhere.
He who receives a benefit with gratitude repays the first instalment
on his debt. There
are some who are not willing to receive a benefit unless it is
privately bestowed; they dislike having a witness to the fact or
anyone aware of it. But these, you may be sure, take a wrong
view. As the giver should add to his gift only that measure of
publicity which will please the one to whom he gives <Ess3-97>
ON BENEFITS, II xxiii. 1-xxiv.2
it, so the recipient should invite the whole
city to witness it; a debt that you are ashamed to acknowledge you
should not accept. Some return their thanks stealthily, in a
corner, in one's ear; this is not discretion, but, in a manner,
repudiation; the man who returns his thanks only when witnesses have
been removed shows himself un-grateful. Some men object to
having any record made of their indebtedness, to the employment of
factors, to the summoning of witnesses to seal the contract, to
giving their bond. These are in the same class with those who take
pains to keep as secret as possible the fact that they have had a
benefit bestowed upon them. They shrink from taking it openly
for fear that they may be said to owe their success to the
assistance of another rather than to their own merit; they are only
rarely found paying their respects to those a to whom they owe their
living or their position, and, while they fear the reputation of
being a dependent, they incur the more painful one of being an
ingrate. Others speak worst of those who have treated them
best. It is safer to offend some men than to have done them a
service; for, in order to prove that they owe nothing, they have
recourse to hatred. And yet nothing ought to be made more
manifest than that services rendered to us linger in our memory, but
the memory must constantly be renewed; for only the man who
remembers is able to repay gratitude, and he who remembers does
thereby repay it. In receiving a benefit we should appear
neither fastidious nor yet submissive and humble; for, if anyone
shows indifference in the act of receiving it, when the whole
benefit is freshly revealed, what will he do when the first pleasure
in it has cooled ? One <Ess3-99>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxiv. 2-xxv. 2
man receives it disdainfully, as if to
say: "I really do not need it, but since you so much wish it,
I will surrender my will to yours"; another accepts listlessly,so
that he leaves the bestower doubtful about his being conscious of
the benefit; still another barely opens his lips, and shows himself
more ungrateful than if he had kept silent. The greater the
favour, the more earnestly must we express ourselves, resorting to
such compliments as: "You have laid more, people under
obligation than you think" (for every one rejoices to know that a
benefit of his extends farther than he thought); "you do not know
what it is that you have bestowed upon me, but you have a right to
know how much more it is than you think" (he who is overwhelmed
shows gratitude forthwith); "I shall never be able to repay to you
my gratitude, but, at any rate, I shall not cease from declaring
everywhere that I am unable to repay it." No single fact more
earned the goodwill of Augustus Caesar, and made it easy for Furnius
to obtain from him other favours than his saying, when Augustus at
his request had granted pardon to his father, who had supported the
side of Antony. "The only injury, Caesar, that I have ever
received from you is this -you have forced me both to live and to
die without expressing my gratitude!" For what so much proves a
grateful heart as the impossibility of ever satisfying oneself, or
of even attaining the hope of ever being able to make adequate
return for a benefit? By these and similar
utterances, instead of concealing, let us try to reveal clearly our
wishes. Though words should fail, yet, if we have the feelings
<Ess3-101>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxi. 3-xxvii. 1
we ought to have, the consciousness of them
will show in our face. The man who intends to be grateful,
immediately, while he is receiving, should turn his thought to
repaying. Such a man, declares Chrysippus, like a racer, who
is all set for the struggle and remains shut up within the barriers,
must await the proper moment to leap forth when, as it were, the
signal has been given; and, truly, he will need to show great
energy, great swiftness, if he is to overtake the other who has the
start of him. And
now we must consider what are the principal causes of
ingratitude. The cause will be either a too high opinion of
oneself and the weakness implanted in mortals of admiring oneself
and one's deeds, or greed, or jealousy. Let us begin with the
first. Every man is a generous judge of himself. {Shylock+} The result is that he
thinks he has deserved all that he gets, and receives it as given in
payment, yet considers that he has not been appraised at nearly his
own value. "He has given me this," he says, "but how late, and
after how much trouble! How much more I might have
accomplished if I had chosen to court So- and-so or So-and-so - or
myself! I had not expected this - I have been-classed with the
herd. Was I worth so little in his eyes? It would have
been more complimentary if he had passed me by!" xxx Gnaeus
Lentulus,/a the augur, who, before his freedmen reduced him to
poverty, was the most conspicuous example of wealth - this man, who
saw his four hundred millions (I have spoken with strict accuracy,
for he did no more than " see" them!), was destitute of
intelligence, as contemptible in intellect as he was <Ess3-103>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxvii. 2-xxviii.
in heart. Though he was the greatest
miser, it was easier for him to disgorge coins than words - so great
was his poverty when it came to talking. Though he owed all his
advancement to the deified Augustus, to whom he had come with
nothing but the poverty that was struggling under the burden of a
noble name, yet, when he had now become the chief citizen of the
state, both in wealth and influence, he used to make constant
complaint, saying that Augustus had enticed him away from his
studies; that he had not heaped upon him nearly so much as he had
lost by surrendering the practice of eloquence. Yet the
deified Augustus besides loading him with other benefits, had also
rescued him from ridicule and vain endeavour! Nor does greed suffer
any man to be grateful; for incontinent hope is never satisfied with
what is given and, the more we get, the more we covet; and just as
the greater the conflagration from which the flame springs, the
fiercer and more unbounded is its fury, so greed becomes much more
active when it is employed in accumulating great riches, And just as little
does ambition suffer any man to rest content with the measure of
public honours that was once his shameless prayer. No one
renders thanks for a tribuneship, but grumbles because he has not
yet been advanced to the praetorship; nor is he grateful for this if
he is still short of the consulship; and even this does not satisfy
him if it is a single one. His greed ever reaches to what is
beyond, and he does not perceive his own happiness because he
regards, not whence he came, but what he would reach. But more
powerful and insistent than all these is the evil of jealousy, which
disquiets us by making comparisons. It argues: "He who
bestowed this on me, <Ess3-105>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxviii. 1-xxix. 1
but more on So-and-so, and an carlier gift
upon So-and-so"; and, too, it pleads no man's case, it is for itself
against everybody. But how much simpler, how much more
sensible it is to magnify the benefit received, to be convinced that
no one is as highly esteemed by another as he is by himself!" I
ought to have received more, but it was not easy for him to give
more; he had to portion out his liberality amongst many others; this
is simply the beginning, let us take it in good part and attract his
notice by accepting it gratefully; he has done too little, but he
will do something oftener; he preferred So-and-so to me, and me to
many others; So-and-so is not my equal either in virtue or in
services, but he has a charm of his own; by complaining I shall
show, not that I am deserving of greater favours, but that I am
undeserving of those that have been given. More favours have
been given to the basest of men, but what does it matter? How rarely
is Fortune judicious! Every day we complain that the wicked
are prosperous; often the hail-storm that has passed over the fields
of the greatest sinners smites the corn of the most upright men;
each one must endure his lot, in friendship as well as in everything
else." No benefit is so ample that it will not be possible for
malice to belittle it, none is so scanty that it cannot be enlarged
by kindly interpretation. Reasons for complaint will never be
lacking if you view benefits on their unfavourable side. See how unjust men are
in appraising the gifts of the gods, even those who profess to be
philosophers./a {Epicureans+}
They grumble because we are inferior to elephants in size of body,
to stags in swiftness, to birds in lightness, to bulls in energy;
because the skin of beasts is tough, <Ess3-107>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxix. 1-5
that of deer more comely, of bears thicker,
of beavers softer than ours; because dogs surpass us in keenness of
scent, eagles in sharpness of vision, crows in length of life, and
many creatures in the ability to swim. And, though Nature does
not suffer certain qualities, as for instance speed of body and
strength, even to meet in the same creature, yet they call it an
injustice that man has not been compounded of various good qualities
that are incompatible, and say that the gods are neglectful of us
because we have not been given the good health that can withstand
even the assaults of vice, because we have not been gifted with a
knowledge of the future. Scarcely can they restrain themselves from
mounting to such a pitch of impertinence as actually to hate Nature
because we mortals are inferior to the gods, because we are not
placed, on an equality with them. But how much better would it
be to turn to the contemplation of our many great blessings, and to
render thanks to the gods because they were pleased to allot to us a
position second only to their own in this most beautiful
dwelling-place, because they have appointed us to be the lords of
earth! Will anyone compare us with the creatures over whom we have
absolute power? Nothing has been denied us that could possibly have
been granted to us.{Best_of_all_possible+} Accordingly,
whoever thou art, thou unfair critic of the lot of mankind, consider
what great blessings, our Father has bestowed upon us, how much more
powerful than ourselves are the creatures we have forced to wear the
yoke, how much swifter those that we are able to catch, how nothing
that dies has been placed beyond the reach of our weapons. So many,
virtues have we received, so many arts, in fine, the <Ess3-109>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxix. 5-xxx. 2
human mind, to which nothing is inaccessible
the moment it makes the effort, which is swifter than the stars
whose future courses through many ages it anticipates; then, too,
all the products of the field, all the store of wealth, and all the
other blessings that are piled one upon the other. Though you
should range through all creation, and, because you will fail to
find there nothing which as a whole you would rather have been,
should select from all creatures the particular qualities that you
could wish had been given to you, yet any right estimate of the
kindliness of Nature will force you to acknowledge that you have
been her darling. The fact is, the immortal gods have held -
still hold - us most dear, and in giving us a place next to
themselves have bestowed upon us the greatest honour that was
possible. Great things have we received, for greater we had no
room. {Essay_on_Man_I+} These considerations,
my dear Liberalis, I have thought necessary because, on the one
hand, when speaking of insignificant benefits, I was forced to speak
also of those that are supreme, and because, on the other, the
abominable presumptuousness of the vice under consideration extends
from these to all benefits. For, if a man scorns the highest
benefits, to whom will he respond with gratitude, what gift will he
deem either great or worthy of being returned? If a man denies
that he has received from the gods the gift of life that he begs
from them every day, to whom will he be indebted for his
preservation, to whom for the breath that he draws? Whoever,
therefore, teaches men to be grateful, pleads the cause both of men
and of the gods, to whom, although there is no thing that they have
need of since they have been placed beyond <Ess3-111>
ON BENEFITS, II xxx. 2-xxxi. 3
all desire; we can nevertheless offer our
gratitude. No one is justified in making his weakness and his
poverty an excuse for ingratitude, in saying: "What am I to do, and
how begin? When can I ever repay to my superiors, who are the
lords of creation, the gratitude that is due?" It is easy to repay
it - without expenditure if you are miserly, without labour if you
are lazy. In fact, the very moment you have been placed under
obligation, you can match favour for favour with any man if you wish
to do so; for he who receives a benefit gladly has already returned
it. This, in my
opinion, is the least surprising or least incredible of the paradox
of the Stoic school: that he who receives a benefit gladly has
already returned it. For, since we Stoics refer every action
to the mind, a man acts only as he wills; and, since devotion, good
faith, justice, since, in short, every virtue is complete within
itself even if it has not been permitted to put out a hand, a man
can also have gratitude by the mere act of will. Again,
whenever anyone attains what he aimed at, he receives the reward of
his effort. When a man bestows a benefit, what does he aim
at? To be of service and to give pleasure to the one to whom
he gives. If he accomplishes what he wished, if his intention
is conveyed to me and stirs in me a joyful response, he gets what he
sought. For he had no wish that I should give him anything in
exchange. Otherwise, it would have been, not a benefaction,
but a bargaining. A man has had a successful voyage if he
reaches the port for which he set out; a dart hurled by a sure hand
performs its duty if it strikes the mark; he who gives a benefit
wishes it to be gratefully accepted; if it is cheerfully <Ess3-113>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxxi. 3-xxxii. 3
received he gets what he wanted.
"But," you say, "he wished to gain something besides!" Then it was
not a benefit, for the chief mark of one is that it carries no
thought of a return. {Gift+} That which I have received I
received in the same spirit in which it was given thus I have made
return. Otherwise, this best of things is subjected to the worst
possible condition in order to show gratitude, I must turn to
Fortune! If I can make no other response because she is
adverse, the answer from heart to heart is enough. "What, then," you
say, "shall I make no effort to return whatever I can, shall I not
hunt for the right time and opportunity, and be eager to fill the
pocket of the one from whom I have received?" Yes, but truly
benefaction is in a sorry state if a man may not have gratitude even
if his hands are empty! "He who has received a
benefit," you say, although he may have received it in the most
generous spirit, has not yet fulfilled his whole duty, for the part
of returning it still remains; just as in playing ball there is some
merit in catching the ball with adroitness and accuracy, yet a man
is not said to be a really good player unless he is clever and
prompt in sending back the ball that he has received." But your
example is not well taken; and why? Because success in the
game depends, not upon the mind of the player, but upon the motion
and the agility of his body, and so an exhibition of which the eye
is to be the judge must be shown in its entirety. Yet, for all
that, I am not willing to say that a man who caught the ball as he
ought was not a good player if, through no fault of his own, he was
prevented from sending it back. "But," you say, "although <Ess3-115>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxxii. 3-xxxiii. 3
the player may not be lacking in skill
since, while he did only half of his duty, the half that he did not
do he is able to do, yet the placing itself remains imperfect, for
its perfection lies in the interchange of throwing backwards and
forwards." I do not wish to refute the point further; let us agree
to this, that, not the player, but the playing, lacks something; so
also in this matter which we are now discussing, the object given
lacks something, for another corresponding to it is still due, but
the spirit of the gift lacks nothing, for it has discovered on the
other side a corresponding spirit, and, so far as the purpose of the
giver is concerned, it has accomplished all that it wished. A benefit has been
bestowed upon me; I have received it in precisely the spirit in
which the giver wished it to be received: he consequently has the
reward he seeks, and the only reward he seeks therefore I show
myself grateful. There remain after this his use of me and
some advantage from having a person grateful; but this comes, not as
the remainder of a duty only partially fulfilled, but as an addition
consequent to its fulfillment. Phidias makes a statue; the
fruit of his art is one thing, that of the artistic product another;
that of his art lies in his having made what he wished to make, that
of the artistic product in his having made it to some profit; the
work of Phidias was completed even if it was not sold. The
fruit of his work he finds is threefold: the first is the
consciousness of it; this he experiences, after the completion of
his work; another is the glory of it; a third is the benefit which
he will gain either from recognition or from the sale of it or from
some other advantage. In the same way the <Ess3-117>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxxiii. 3-xxxiv. 3
first fruit of a benefaction is the
consciousness of it a man experiences this from carrying out his
gift as he wished; the second and the third are, respectively, the
glory of it and the things which may be bestowed in exchange.
And so, when a benefit has been graciously received, the giver has
forthwith received gratitude in return, but not yet his full reward;
my indebtedness, therefore, is for something apart from the benefit,
for the benefit itself I have repaid in full by cheerfully accepting
it. xxx "What, then?" you say, "does a man repay gratitude by doing
nothing?" But he has done the chief thing - by showing a good spirit
he has conferred a good, and - what is the mark of friendship - in
equal measure. Then, in the second place, a benefit is paid in
one way, a loan in another; there is no reason why you should expect
me to flourish the payment before your eyes - the transaction is
performed in our minds! You will come to see
that what I am saying is not too bold, although at first it may not
accord with your own ideas, if only you will give me your attention,
and reflect that there are many things for which there are no
words. There is a vast number of things that have no name, and
the terms by which we designate them, instead of being their own,
belong to other things from which they are borrowed. We say
that we ourselves, a couch, a sail, and a poem, have a "foot," and
we apply the word "dog" to a hound, to a creature of the sea, and to
a constellation; since there are not enough words to make it
possible for us to assign a separate one to each separate thing, we
borrow whenever it becomes necessary. Bravery is the virtue that
scorns legitimate dangers, or knowing how to <Ess3-119>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxxiv. 3-xxxv. 2
ward off, to meet, and to court dangers; yet
we call both a gladiator and the worthless slave whose rashness has
forced him into scorn of death a "brave" man. Frugality is
knowing how to avoid unnecessary expenditure, or the art of applying
moderation to the use of private means; yet we call a petty-minded
and close-fisted man a very "frugal" person although there is an
infinite difference between moderation and meanness. These are
essentially different things, yet our poverty of language leads us
to call each of the two types a "frugal" person, and likewise to say
that both the man who by the exercise of reason scorns the blows of
Fortune and the one who rushes into dangers unreasoningly are
"brave." So a "benefit," as we have said, is both a beneficent act
and likewise the object itself which is given by means of the
aforesaid act, as money, a house, the robe of office; the two things
bear the same name, but they are very different in their import and
operation. Attend,
therefore, and you will soon understand that I am advancing nothing
that your own conviction will reject. For the benefit that is
accomplished by an act has been repaid by our gratitude if we give
it friendly welcome; the other, which consists of some object, we
have not yet returned, but we shall have the desire to return
it. Goodwill we have repaid with goodwill; for the object we
still owe an object. And so, although we say that he who
receives a benefit gladly has repaid it, we, nevertheless, also bid
him return some gift similar to the one he received. Some of the utterances
that we Stoics make avoid the ordinary meaning of the terms, and
then by a different line of thought are restored to their ordinary
<Ess3-121>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxxv. 2-5
meaning. We deny that the wise man can
receive injury, yet the man who strikes him with his fist will be
sentenced on the charge of doing him an injury; we deny that a fool
possesses anything, and yet a man who steals some object from a fool
will be punished for theft; we declare that all men are mad, and yet
we do not dose all men with hellebore; and to the very men whom we
call mad we entrust the right of suffrage and the jurisdiction of
judge. {Swift+} So we declare that he who receives
a benefit in a kindly spirit has repaid it by gratitude, yet,
nevertheless, we leave him in debt - still bound to repay gratitude
even after he has repaid it. The aim of this is, not to forbid
beneficence, but to encourage us not to be fearful of benefits, not
to faint under them as if we were weighed down by an intolerable
burden. "Good things," you exclaim, "have been given to me, my
reputation has been protected, my ignominy has been removed, my life
has been preserved, and my liberty that is dearer than life.
And how shall I ever be able to repay my gratitude? When will
there come the day on which I can show to my benefactor my heart?"
This is the very day - the day on which he is showing his own
heart! Accept the benefit, embrace it, rejoice, not because
you are receiving it, but because you are returning it and yet will
still be in debt; you will then avoid the risk of the great mishap
that some chance may cause you to be ungrateful. No difficult
terms will I set before you for fear that you may be discouraged,
that you may faint at the prospect of long labour and
servitude. I do not put you off - you may pay with what you
have! Never will you be grateful if you are not so at this
moment. What, then, shall you do? There is no need for you to
take up <Ess3-123>
ON BENEFITS, II. xxxv. 5
arms - perhaps some day there will be.
There is no need for you to traverse the seas - perhaps some day you
will ret sail even when storm-winds are threatening. Do you
wish to return a benefit? Accept it with pleasure; you have
repaid it by gratitude - not so fully that you may feel that you
have freed yourself from debt, yet so that you may be less concerned
about what you still owe!
<Ess3-125>
BOOK III
NOT to return gratitude for benefits is a
disgrace, and the whole world counts it as such, Aebutius
Liberalis. Therefore even the ungrateful complain of
ingratitude, while the vice that all find so distasteful
nevertheless continues its hold upon all, and we go so far to the
opposite extreme that sometimes, not merely after having received
benefits, but because we have received them, we consider the givers
our worst enemies. I cannot deny that, while some fall into
the vice from a natural perversity, more show it because remembrance
disappears with the passing of time for benefits that at first lived
fresh in their memory wither as the days go by. On the subject
of such persons you and I, I am well aware, have already had a
discussion, in which you said that they were, not ungrateful, but
forgetful; just as if that which caused a man to be ungrateful could
be any excuse for his being so, or as if the fact that a man had
this misfortune kept him from being ungrateful, whereas it is only
the ungrateful man who has this misfortune. There are many sorts
of ungrateful men, just as there are many sorts of thieves and of
murderers - they all show the same sin, but their types the greatest
diversity. The man is ungrateful who denies that he has
received a benefit, which he has in fact received; he is ungrateful
who pretends that he has <Ess3-127>
ON BENEFITS, III. i. 3-ii. 2
not received one; he, too, is ungrateful who
fails to return one; but the most ungrateful of all is the man who
has forgotten a benefit. For the others, even if they do not
pay, continue in debt, and reveal at least some trace of the
services that they have locked in the depths of their evil
hearts. These, it may be, for one reason or another, may some
day turn to the expression of gratitude, whether urged to it by
shame, or by the sudden impulse toward honourable action that is
wont to spring up for a moment even in the hearts of bad men, or
perhaps by the call of a favorable opportunity. But there is
no possibility of a man's ever becoming grateful, if he has lost all
memory of his benefit. And which of the two would you call the
worse - the man whose heart is dead to gratitude for a benefit, or
the one whose heart is dead even to the memory of a benefit?
Eyes that shrink from the light are weak, those that cannot see are
blind; and not to love one's parents is to be unfilial, not to
recognize them is to be mad! Who is so ungrateful
as the man who has so completely excluded and cast from his mind the
benefit that ought to have been kept uppermost in his thought and
always before him, as to have lost all knowledge of it? It is
evident that he has not thought very often about returning it if it
has faded into oblivion. In short, the repaying of gratitude
requires right desire and opportunity and means and the favour of
Fortune; but he who remembers shows sufficient gratitude without any
outlay. Since this duty demands neither effort nor wealth nor
good fortune, he who fails to render it has no excuse in which he
may find shelter; for he who has thrust a <Ess3-129>
ON BENEFITS, III. ii. 2-iii. 3
benefit so far from him that he has actually
lost sight of it never could have wished to be grateful for
it. Just as tools that are in use and are every day subjected
to the contact of our hands never run any risk of becoming rusty,
while those that are not brought before the eyes, and, not being
required, have remained apart from constant use, gather rust from
the mere passing of time, so anything that our thought repeatedly
busies itself with and keeps fresh does not slip from the memory,
which loses only that which it has over and over again failed to
regard. xxx Besides this, there are still other causes that tend to
uproot from our minds services that sometimes have been very
great. The first and most powerful of all is the fact that,
busied as we are with ever new desires, we turn our eyes, not to
what we possess but to what we seek to possess. To those who are
intent upon something they wish to gain all that they have already
gained seems worthless. It follows too, that, when the desire
of new benefits has diminished the value of one that has already
been received, the author of them also is less esteemed. We
love someone, and look up to him, and avow that he laid the
foundation of our present position so long as we are satisfied with
what we have attained; then the desirability of other things assails
our mind, and we rush toward those, as is the way of mortals, who,
having great things, always desire greater. And everything
that we were formerly inclined to call a benefit straightway slips
from our memory, and we turn our eyes, not to the things that have
set us above others, but to the things that the good fortune of
those who outstrip us displays. But it is possible for no man
to show envy and gratitude at <Ess3-131>
ON BENEFITS, III. iii. 3-v. 1
the same time, for envy goes with complaint
and unhappiness, gratitude with rejoicing. In the second place,
because each one of us is actually aware of only the particular
moment of time that is passing, only now and then do men turn their
thought back to the past; so it happens that the memory of our
teachers and of their benefits to us vanishes because we have left
boyhood wholly behind; so, too, it happens that the benefits
conferred upon us in youth are lost because youth itself is never
relived. No one regards what has been as something that has passed,
but as something that has perished, and so the memory of those who
are intent upon a future benefit is weak. At this point I must
bear testimony to Epicurus, who constantly complains because we are
ungrateful for past blessings, because we do not recall those that
we have enjoyed, nor count them in the list of pleasures, while no
pleasure exists more certainly than one that can no longer be
snatched away. Present blessings are not yet wholly
established upon a firm basis, it is still possible that some
mischance may interrupt them; future blessings are still in the air
and are uncertain; but what is past has been stored away in
safety. How can a man who is wholly absorbed in the present
and the future, who skips over all his past life, ever be grateful
for benefits? It is memory that makes him grateful; the more
time one gives to hope, the less one has for memory. There are
some subjects, my dear Liberalis, that remain fixed in our memory
when we have once grasped them, and others that, if they are to be
known, require more than a first acquaintance provides (for
knowledge of them is lost unless it is con- <Ess3-33>
ON BENEFITS, III. v. I-vi. 2
tinued) - l am thinking of the knowledge of
geometry and of the motions of the heavenly bodies and of other
similar subjects that, on account of their nicety, have a slippery
hold. Just so, in the matter of benefits, there are some whose
very magnitude will not allow them to slip from our mind, while
others that are smaller, yet countless in number and bestowed at
various times, escape from our memory because, as I have said, we do
not repeatedly revert to them, and are not glad to recognize what we
owe to each. Listen to the words of petitioners. No one
of them fails to say that the memory of the benefit will live for
ever in his heart; no one of them fails to declare himself your
submissive and devoted slave, and, if he can find any more abject
language in which to express his obligation, he uses it. But
after a very little time these same men avoid their earlier
utterances, counting them degrading and unworthy of a free man; and
then they reach the state, to which, in my opinion, all the worst
and the most ungrateful men come - they grow forgetful. For so
surely is he ungrateful who has forgotten that a man is ungrateful
when a benefit only "comes into his mind." xxxSome raise the
question whether a vice so odious as this ought to go unpunished, or
whether this law, by which, as it operates in the schools,/a the
ungrateful man becomes liable to prosecution, ought to be applied
also in the state; for it seems to everybody to be a just one.
"Why not?" they say, "since even cities bring charges against cities
for services rendered, and force later generations to pay for what
had been bestowed upon their forefathers." But our forefathers, who
were undoubtedly very great men, demanded restitution only from
their enemies; <Ess3-135>
ON BENEFITS, III. vi. 2-vii. 3
benefactions they would bestow
magnanimously, and lose them magnanimously. With the exception of
the people of Macedonia,/a in no state has the ungrateful man become
liable to prosecution. And ample proof that there ought not to
have been any such liability is shown by the fact that we are in
full accord in opposing all crime; the penalty for homicide, for
poisoning, for parricide, and for the desecration of religion is
different in different places, but they have some penalty
everywhere, whereas this crime that is the commonest of all is
nowhere punished, but is everywhere denounced. And yet we have not
wholly acquitted it, but, because it is difficult to form an opinion
of a thing so uncertain, we have only condemned it to hatred, and
have left it among the sins that are referred to the gods for
judgement. But
many reasons occur to me why this crime should not come under the
law. First of all, the best part of a benefit is lost if it
can become actionable, as is possible in the case of a fixed loan or
of something rented or leased. For the most beautiful part of
a benefit is that we gave it even when we were likely to lose it,
that we left it wholly to the discretion of the one who received
it. If I arrest him, if I summon him before a judge, it gets
to be, not a benefit, but a loan. In the second place,
although to repay gratitude is a most praiseworthy act, it ceases to
be praiseworthy if it is made obligatory; for in that case no one
will any more praise a man for being grateful than he will praise
one who has returned a deposit of money, or paid a debt without
being summoned before a judge. So we spoil the two most
beautiful things in human life - a man's gratitude and a man's
benefit. For what nobility does either one show - the one if,
instead of <Ess3-137>
ON BENEFITS, III. vii. 3-7
giving, he lends a benefit, the other if he
makes return, not because he wishes, but because he is forced?
There is no glory in being grateful unless it would have been safe
to be ungrateful.
Add, too, the fact that for the application of this one law all the
law-courts in the world would scarcely be enough! Where is the man
who will not bring action? Where is the man against whom
action will not be brought? For all exalt their own merits,
all magnify the smallest services they have rendered to others. Again, in all matters
that become the basis of legal action it is possible to define/a the
procedure and to prohibit the judge from unlimited liberty; it is
clear, accordingly, that a just case is in a better position if it
is brought before a judge than if it is brought before an "arbiter,"
because the judge is restricted by the formula of instructions,
which sets definite bounds that he cannot exceed, whereas the other
has entire liberty of conscience and is hampered by no bonds; he can
lessen the value of some fact or augment it, and can regulate his
opinion, not according to the dictates of law or justice, but
according to the promptings of humanity or pity. But an action
for ingratitude would not place any restriction on the judge, but
would set him in a position of absolutely untrammeled
authority. For it is not clearly determined what a benefit is,
nor, too, how great it is; that depends upon how generously the
judge may interpret it. No law shows what an ungrateful person
is; often one who has returned what he received is ungrateful, and
one who has not returned it is grateful, On certain matters even an
inexperienced judge is able to give a verdict; for instance, when an
opinion must be <Ess3-139>
ON BENEFITS, III. vii. 7-viii. 3
delivered on whether something has, or has
not, been done, when the dispute is terminated by the giving of
bonds, when common sense pronounces judgement between the
litigants. When, however, a conjecture of motive has to be
made, when a point concerning which wisdom alone can decide happens
to be in dispute, it cannot be that for such purposes a judge is to
be taken from the general crowd of jurors/a - a man whom income and
the inheritance of equestrian fortune have placed upon the roll, Therefore the truth
is, not that this offence has appeared quite unfitted to be brought
before a judge, but that no one has been found who was quite fitted
to be its judge; and this will cause you no surprise if you will
thresh out all the difficulties that anyone would have if he should
appear against a man arraigned on a charge of this sort. A
gift has been made by someone of a large sum of money, but the giver
was rich, he was not likely to feel the sacrifice; the same gift was
made by another, but the giver was likely to lose the whole of his
patrimony. The sum given is the same, but the benefit is not
the same. Take another case. Suppose a man paid out money for
one who had been adjudged to his creditor, but in doing so drew from
his own private means; another gave the same amount, but borrowed it
or begged it, and in doing a great service was willing to burden
himself with an obligation. Do you think that the one, for
whom it was easy to bestow a benefit, and the other, who received in
order that he might give a benefit, are both in the same
class? The timeliness, not the size, of a gift makes some
benefits great. It is a benefit to bestow the gift of an estate that
by reason of its fertility may lower the price of grain, it <Ess3-141>
ON BENEFITS, III. viii. 3-ix. 2
is a benefit to bestow one loaf of bread in
time of famine; it is a benefit to bestow lands that have large and
navigable rivers flowing through them; it is a benefit to point out
a spring of water to a man when he is parched with thirst and can
scarcely draw breath through his dry throat. Who will match these
one against another? Who will weigh them in the balance? The
decision is difficult when it is concerned, not with the thing, but
with the significance of the thing. Though the gifts are the
same, if they are differently given their weight is not the
same. A man may have bestowed on me a benefit, but suppose he
did not do it willingly, suppose he complained about having bestowed
it, suppose he regarded me more haughtily than was his wont, suppose
he was so slow to give that he would have conferred a greater
service if he had been quick to refuse. How will a judge set
about appraising these benefits when the giver's words, his
hesitation, and expression may destroy all gratitude for his
favour? And what shall we say of some gifts that are called
benefits because they are excessively coveted, while others, though
they lack this common ear-mark, are really greater benefits even if
the do not appear so? It is called a "benefit" if you have
given someone the citizenship of a powerful people, if you have
escorted him to the fourteen rows/a of the knights, if you have
defended him when he was on trial for his life. But what of
having given him useful advice? What of having kept him from
plunging into crime? What of having struck the sword from his
hands when he planned to die? What of having brought him
effective consolation in sorrow, and of having restored <Ess3-143>
ON BENEFITS, III. ix. 2-x. 3
in him a resolve to live when he was wishing
to follow those for whom he grieved? What of having sat at his
side when he was sick, and, when his health and recovery were a
matter of moments, of having seized the right times to administer
food, of having revived his failing pulse with wine, and brought in
a physician when he was dying? Who will estimate the value of
such services? Who will decree that benefits of one sort
counterbalance benefits of another? "I gave you a house," you
say. Yes, but I warned you that yours was tumbling down upon
your head! "I gave you a fortune," you say. Yes, but I
gave you a plank when you were shipwrecked! "I fought for you
and received wounds for your sake," you say. Yes, but I by my
silence gave you your life! Since benefits may be given in one
form and repayed in another, it is difficult to establish their
equality. Besides,
for the repayment of a benefit no date is set, as there is for a
loan of money; and so it is possible that one who has not yet repaid
may still repay. Pray tell me, at the expiration of what time
is a man to be arrested for ingratitude? Of the greatest
benefits there is no visible evidence; they often lie hidden in a
silent consciousness that only two share. Or shall we
introduce the rule of not giving a benefit without a witness? And then what
punishment shall we fix upon for the ungrateful? Shall there
be the same one for all though their benefits are unequal? Or
shall it be variable, a larger or smaller one according to the
benefit each one has received? Very well, then, the standard
of evaluation shall be money. But what of some benefits that
have the value of life or are even greater than life? What
punishment will be pro- <Ess3-145>
ON BENEFITS, III. x. 3-xi. 2
nounced upon ingratitude for these?
One smaller than the benefit? That would be unjust! One
that is its equal - death? But what could be more inhuman than
that benefits should end in bloodshed? "Certain
prerogatives," it is argued, "have been accorded to parents; and, in
the same way in which the case of these has been considered to be
exceptional, the case of other benefactors must also be considered
to be so." But we have given sanctity to the position of parents
because it was expedient that they should rear children; it was
necessary to encourage them to the task because they were going to
face an uncertain hazard. You could not say to them what you
say to those who give benefits: "Choose the one to whom you
will give; you have only yourself to blame if you have been
deceived; help the deserving man." In the rearing of children
nothing is left to the choice of those who rear them - it is wholly
a matter of hope. And so, in order that parents might be more
content to run the risk, it was necessary to give to them a certain
authority. Then,
too, the situation of parents is very different for to those to whom
they have already given they none the less give, and will continue
to give, benefits, nor is there any danger of their making false
claims about having given them. In the case of other
benefactors there must be the question not only of whether they have
received a return, but also of whether they have actually given,
while in the case of parents their services are unquestionable, and,
because it is expedient that the young should be controlled, we have
placed over them household magistrates, as it were, under whose
custody they may be held in check. <Ess3-147>
ON BENEFITS, III. xi. 3-xii. 3 Again, the
benefit from a parent was the same for all, and so it could be
evaluated once for all. Benefits from others are diverse in
character, are unrelated and separated from each by incalculable
distances; and so they could not be brought under any fixed norm,
since it was more equitable to leave all unclassified than to place
them all in the same category. Certain benefits cost
the givers a great price, others have great value in the eyes of the
recipients, but cost the bestowers of them nothing. Some are
given to friends, some to strangers; although the same amount is
given, it counts for more if it is given to one with whom the
beginning of an acquaintance dates from the gift of your benefit.
This one bestowed help, that other distinctions, another
consolations. You will find the person who thinks that there is no
greater pleasure, no greater boon than to have some breast on which
he may find rest in misfortune; again, you will find another who
would prefer to have concern shown for his prestige rather than for
his security; there is the man, too, who will feel more indebted to
one who adds to his safety than to his honour. Consequently,
these benefits will assume greater or less value according as the
temper of the judge leans in the one direction or the other.
Moreover, while I myself choose my creditor, yet I often receive a
benefit from one from whom I do not wish it, and sometimes even
unwillingly I contract an obligation. What in this case will you
do? Will you call a man ungrateful when, without his knowing
it, a benefit has been forced upon him which had he known it, he
would not have accepted? Will you not call him ungrateful if
he does not repay it, no matter how he may have received it?
Suppose that <Ess3-149>
ON BENEFITS, III. xii. 4-xiv. 2
someone has bestowed upon me a benefit, and
that the same man later has done me an injury. Am I bound to
endure every sort of injury because of his one gift, or will it be
the same as if I had repaid his favour because he himself cancelled
the benefit by his later injury? And then how will you tell
whether the benefit that he received or the injury was the greater?
Time will fail me if I attempt to enumerate all the
difficulties. "By not coming to the defence of benefits that
have been given, and, by not inflicting punishment on those who deny
them, we only make men more reluctant," you say, "to bestow others."
But, on the other hand, remember, too, that men will be much more
reluctant to accept benefits if they are going to run the risk of
being forced to defend their case in court, and of having their
integrity placed in a very dubious position. Then, too, we
ourselves, because of this possibility, will be more reluctant to
give; for no one gives willingly to the unwilling recipient, but
every one, whose own goodness and the very beauty of his action has
urged him to perform a generous deed, will give even more willingly
to those who will incur no indebtedness except what they wish to
feel. For a good deed that looks carefully to its own
interests loses some of its glory. Then, again, while
benefits will become fewer, they will be more genuine; but what harm
is there in checking the reckless giving of benefits? For the
very aim of those who have designed no law for this matter has been
that we should be more cautious in making gifts, more cautious in
picking those upon whom we bestow our favours. Consider again
and again to whom you are giving: you will have no <Ess3-151>
ON BENEFITS, III. xiv. 2-xv. 2
recourse to law, no claim to
restitution. You are mistaken if you think that some judge
will come to your aid; no law will restore you to your original
estate - look only to the good faith of the recipient. In this
way benefits maintain their prestige and are lordly; you disgrace
them if you make them the ground of litigation. "Pay what you
owe" is a proverb most just and one that is stamped with the
approval of all nations; but in the case of a benefit it becomes
most shameful. "Pay!" But what? Shall a man pay the life
that he owes? The position? The security? The
sound health? All the greatest benefits are incapable of being
repaid. "Yet make some return for them," you say, "that is of
equal value." But this is just what I was saying, that, if we make
merchandise of benefits, all the merit of so fine an action will
perish. The mind does not need to be incited to greed, to
accusations, and to discord; it tends to these by a natural
impulse. But, as far as we can, let us oppose it, and cut it
off from the opportunities that it seeks. Would that I could
persuade the lenders of money to accept payment only from those who
are willing to pay! Would that no compact marked the
obligation of buyer to seller, and that no covenants and agreements
were safeguarded by the impress of seals, but that, instead, the
keeping of them were left to good faith and a conscience that
cherishes justice! But men have preferred what is necessary to
what is best, and would rather compel good faith than expect
it. Witnesses are summoned on both sides. One creditor,
by having recourse to factors, causes the record to be made in the
books of several people; another is not content with oral promises,
but must <Ess3-153>
ON BENEFITS, III. xv. 3-xvi. 2
also bind his victim by a written
signature. O, what a shameful admission of the dishonesty and
wickedness of the human race! More trust is placed in our
sealrings than in our consciences. To what end have these
notable men been summoned? To what end do they leave the
impress of their signets? In order, forsooth, that the debtor may
not deny that what he has received has been received! Think
you that these men are incorruptible and champions of truth?
Yet to these very men money will not be entrusted at this hour on
any other terms. So would it not have been more desirable to
allow some men to break their word than to cause all men to fear
treachery? The only thing that avarice lacks now is that we
should not even give benefits without a bondsman! To help, to
be of service, is the part of a noble and chivalrous soul; he who
gives benefits imitates the gods, he who seeks a return,
money-lenders. Why, in wishing to protect benefactors, do we reduce
them to the level of the most disreputable class? {Shylock+} xxx" More men," you
say, "will become ungrateful if no action can be brought against
ingratitude." No, fewer men, because benefits will be given with a
greater discrimination. Then, too, it is not advisable that all men
should know how many are ungrateful for the multitude of the
offenders will remove the shame of the thing, and what is a general
reproach will cease to be a disgrace. Is there any woman that
blushes at divorce now that certain illustrious and noble ladies
reckon their years, not by the number of consuls, but by the number
of their husbands, and leave home in order to marry, and marry in
order to be divorced? They shrank from this scandal as long as
it was rare; now, since every gazette has a <Ess3-155>
ON BENEFITS, III. xvi. 2-xvii. 3
divorce case, they have learned to do what
they used to hear so much about. Is there any shame at all for
adultery now that matters have come to such a pass that no woman has
any use for a husband except to inflame her paramour? Chastity
is simply a proof of ugliness. Where will you find any woman
so wretched, so unattractive, as to be content with a couple of
paramours - without having each hour assigned to a different
one? And the day is not long enough for them all, but she must
be carried in her litter to the house of one, and spend the night
with another. She is simple and behind the times who is not
aware that living with one paramour is called "marriage"! As
the shame of these offences has disappeared now that their practice
has spread more broadly, so you will make ingrates more numerous and
increase their importance if once they begin to count their number.
"What, then," you
say, "shall the ingrate go unpunished?" What, then, shall the
undutiful man go unpunished? And the spiteful? And the
greedy? And the overbearing? And the cruel? Do you
imagine that qualities that are loathed do go unpunished, or that
there is any greater punishment than public hate? The penalty
of the ingrate is that he does not dare to accept a benefit-from any
man, that he does not dare to give one to any man, that he is a
mark, or at least thinks that he is a mark, for all eyes, that he
has lost all perception of a most desirable and pleasant
experience. Or do you call that man unhappy who has lost his
sight, whose ears have been closed by some malady, and yet do not
call him wretched who has lost all sense of benefits? He
dwells in fear of the gods, who are the witnesses of all <Ess3-157>
ON BENEFITS, III. xvii. 3-xviii. I
ingratitude, he is tortured and distressed
by the consciousness of having thwarted a benefit. In short,
this in itself is punishment great enough, the fact that he does not
reap enjoyment from an experience that, as I just said, is the most
delightful. But he
who is happy in having received a benefit tastes a constant and
unfailing pleasure, and rejoices in viewing, not the gift, but the
intention of him from whom he received it. The grateful man
delights in a benefit over and over, the ungrateful man but
once. But is it possible to compare the lives of these
two? For the one, as a disclaimer of debts and a cheat are apt
to be, is downcast and worried, he denies to his parents, to his
protector, to his teachers, the consideration that is their due,
while the other is joyous, cheerful, and, watching for an
opportunity to repay his gratitude, derives great joy from this very
sentiment, and seeks, not how he may default in his obligations, but
how he may make very full and rich return, not only to his parents
and friends, but also to persons of lower station. For, even
if he has received a benefit from his slave, he considers, not from
whom it came, but what he received. xxx And yet some raise the
question, for example Hecaton, whether it is possible for a slave to
give a benefit to his master. For there are those who
distinguish some acts as benefits, some as duties, some as services,
saying that a benefit is something that is given by a stranger (a
stranger is one who, without incurring censure, might have done
nothing); that a duty is performed by a son, or a wife, or by
persons that are stirred by the ties of kinship, which impels them
to bear aid; that a service is contributed by a slave, whose
condition has placed him in such a <Ess3-159>
ON BENEFITS, III. xviii. i-xix. I
position that nothing that he can bestow
gives him a claim upon his superior. Moreover, he who denies
that a slave can sometimes give a benefit to his master is ignorant
of the rights of man; for, not the status, but the intention, of the
one who bestows is what counts. Virtue closes the door to no
man; it is open to all, admits all, invites all, the freeborn and
the freedman, the slave and the king, and the exile; neither family
nor fortune determines its choice -it is satisfied with the naked
human being. For what protection would it find against sudden
events, what great assurance would the human mind be able to hold
out to itself if Fortune could rob it of unchangeable Virtue?
If a slave cannot give a benefit to his master, no subject can give
one to his king, no soldier to his general; for, if a man is
restrained by supreme authority, what difference does it make what
the nature of the authority is that restrains him? For, if the
necessity of his lot and his fear of having to endure untold
punishment prevent a slave from attaining the right to do a
thankworthy act, the same condition will also prevent the man who is
un er a king, and the man who is under a general; for these, under a
different title, exercise equal authority. But a man can give
a benefit to his king, a man can give a benefit to his general;
therefore a slave also can give one to a master. It is
possible for a slave to be just, it is possible for him to be brave,
it is possible for him to be magnanimous; therefore it is possible
also for him to give a benefit, for this also is one part of
virtue. {Wyf_of_Bath+} So true is it
that slaves are able to give benefits to their masters that they
have often caused their benefit to be their masters themselves./a
There is no doubt that a slave is able to give a <Ess3-161>
ON BENEFITS, III. xix. 1-4
benefit to anyone he pleases; why not,
therefore, also to his master? "Because," you say, "it is not
possible for him to become his master's 'creditor ' if he has given
him money. Otherwise, he makes his master in debt to him every
day; he attends him when be travels, he nurses him when he is sick,
he expends the greatest labour in cultivating his farm; nevertheless
all these boons, which when supplied by another are called benefits,
are merely I 'services ' when they are supplied by a slave.
For a benefit is someting that some person has given when it was
also within his power not to give it. But a slave does not
have the right to refuse; thus he does not confer, but merely obeys,
and he takes no credit for what he has done because it was not
possible for him to fail to do it." Even under these
conditions I shall still win the day and promote a slave to such a
position that he will, in many respects, be a free man.
Meanwhile, tell me this - if I show to you one who fights for the
safety of his master without any regard for his own, and, pierced
with wounds, pours forth the last drops of his life-blood wn from
his very vitals, who, in order to provide time for his master to
escape, seeks to give him a respite at the cost of his own life,
will you deny that this man has bestowed a benefit simply because he
is a slave? If I show to you one who, refusing to betray to a tyrant
the secrets of his master, was bribed by no promises, terrified by
no threats, overcome by no tortures, and, as far as he was able,
confounded - the suspicions of his questioner, and paid the penalty
of good faith with his life, will you deny that this man bestowed a
benefit on his master simply because he was his slave?
Consider, rather, whether <Ess3-163>
ON BENEFITS, III. xix. 4-xxi. 2
in the case of slaves, a manifestation of
virtue {virtue_in_peasants+} is not the more
praiseworthy the rarer it is, and, too, whether it is not all the
more gratifying that, despite their general aversion to domination
and the irksomeness of constraint, some slave by his affection for
his master has overcome the common hatred of being a slave.
So, therefore, a benefit does not cease to be a benefit because it
proceeded from a slave, but is all the greater on that account,
because he could not be deterred from it even by being a
slave. It is a mistake for anyone to believe that the
condition of slavery penetrates into the whole being of a man.
The better part of him is exempt. Only the body is at the
mercy and disposition of a master; but the mind is its own master,
and is so free and unshackled that not even this prison of the body,
in which it is confined, can restrain it from using its own powers,
following mighty aims, and escaping into the infinite to keep
company with the stars. It is, therefore, the body that
Fortune hands over to a master; it is this that he buys, it is this
that he sells; that inner part cannot be delivered into
bondage. All that issues from this is free; nor, indeed, are
we able to command all things from slaves, nor are they compelled to
obey us in all things; they will not carry out orders that are
hostile to the state, and they will not lend their hands to any
crime. {Freedom+} There are certain acts
that the law neither enjoins nor forbids; it is in these that a
slave finds opportunity to perform a benefit. So long as what
he supplies is only that which is ordinarily required of a slave, it
is a "service"; when he supplies more than a slave need do, it is a
"benefit"; it ceases to be called a service when it passes over into
the domain of friendly <Ess3-165>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxi. 2-xxii. 3
affection. There are certain things,
as for instance food and clothing, which the master must supply to
the slave; no one calls these benefits. But suppose the master is
indulgent, gives him the education of a gentleman, has him taught
the branches in which the freeborn are schooled - all this will be a
benefit. Conversely, the same is true in the case of the
slave. All that he does in excess of what is prescribed as the duty
of a slave, what he supplies, not from obedience to authority, but
from his own desire, will be a benefit, provided that its
importance, if another person were supplying it, would entitle it to
that name. A
slave, according to the definition of Chrysippus, is a "hireling for
life." And, just as a hireling gives a benefit if he supplies more
than he contracted to do, so a slave - when he exceeds the bounds of
his station in goodwill toward his master, and surpasses the
expectation of his master by daring some lofty deed that would be an
honour even to those more happily born, a benefit is found to exist
inside the household. Or do you think it fair that those with
whom we become angry if they do less than they ought should not draw
our gratitude if they do more than they ought or are wont? Do
you want to know when what a slave does is not a benefit? When
one might say of it: "What if he had refused?" But when he has
bestowed something that he had a right to refuse to bestow, the fact
that he was willing deserves to be praised. Benefit and injury
are the opposites of each other it is possible for a slave to give a
benefit to his master if it is possible for him to receive an injury
from his master. But cognizance of the injuries inflicted by masters
upon their slaves has been committed to an <Ess3-167>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxii. 3-xxiii. 2
official who restrains their cruelty and
lust and their stinginess in supplying them with the necessities of
life. What, then, is the case? Does a master receive a
benefit from a slave? No, but a human being from a human
being. After all, whatever was in his power, he did - he gave
a benefit to his master; that you should not receive one from a
slave is in your power. But who is so exalted that Fortune may
not force him to have need of even the most lowly? I shall
proceed now to cite a number of instances of benefits that differ
from each other and are in some cases contradictory. One gave to his
master life, one gave death, one saved him when he was about to
perish, and, if this is not enough, one saved him by perishing
himself; another helped his master to die, another baffled his
desire. Claudius
Quadrigarius relates, in the eighteenth book of his Annals, that,
during the siege of Grumentum, just when the city had reached its
most desperate plight, two slaves deserted to the enemy and there
did good service. Later, after the city had been captured,
while the victors were rushing hither and thither, that the two ran
ahead along the well-known streets to the house in which they had
been slaves, and drove forth their mistress in front of them; that,
if anyone asked who she was, they stated that she had been their
mistress, and, indeed, a most cruel one, and that they were taking
her off to punishment. But that afterwards, when they had
brought her outside the walls, they concealed her with the utmost
care until the fury of the enemy subsided, and later, when the
soldiers, quickly glutted, returned to the normal conduct of Romans,
that they, too, returned to theirs, and of their own accord gave
themselves into the <Ess3-169>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxix. 3-xxxv.
power of their mistress. She
manumitted both on the spot, and did not think it beneath her to
have received her life at the hands of those over whom she had once
had the power of life and death. Instead, she might even have
congratulated herself upon this fact; for, if she had been saved by
other hands, she would have had the mere gift of well-known and
common mercy, but, as it was, she became famous in story, and an
example to two cities. In the great confusion of the city, at
a time when every one was thinking of his own interest, she was
deserted by all except these deserters; but they, playing the role
of being her murderers, deserted from the victors to the captive
lady in order to reveal the purpose that had led them to make their
first desertion; and the crowning touch to their benefit was that,
in order to save the life of their mistress, they thought it was
worth the price of seeming to have put her to death. Believe
me, it is not the act - I will not say of a "slavish," but - of a
commonplace soul to purchase a noble deed at the cost of being
thought a criminal! When Vettius, the
praetor of the Marsians, was being conducted to the Roman general,
his slave snatched a sword from the very soldier who was dragging
him along, and first slew his master. Then he said: "Now that
I have given my master his freedom, the time has come for me to
think also of myself," and so with one blow he stabbed himself. Name
to me anyone who has saved his master more gloriously. When Caesar was
besieging Corfinium, Domitius, who was confined in the city by the
blockade, ordered one of his slaves, who was likewise his physician,
to give him poison. Observing his reluctance, he said: <Ess3-171>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxiv.-xxvi. 1
"Why do you hesitate, as though this matter
were wholly in your own power; I am asking for death, but I have my
sword." Whereupon the slave assented, and gave him a concoction to
drink that was harmless. When Domitius had fallen asleep
because of it, the slave went to his master's son, and said:
"Have me put under guard until you discover from the outcome whether
I have given your father poison." Domitius did not die, and Caesar
saved his life but his life had first been saved by a slave. During the Civil War,
a slave hid away his master, who had been proscribed, and, having
put on his rings and dressed himself in his clothes, presented
himself to those searching for his master, and, saying that he asked
for nothing better than that they should carry out their orders,
forthwith offered his neck for their swords. What a hero! - to
wish to die in place of a master in times when not to wish a master
to die was a rare show of loyalty; to be found kind when the state
was cruel, faithful when it was treacherous; to covet death as a
reward for loyalty in face of the huge rewards that are offered for
disloyalty! And I will not omit some example from our own
age. Under Tiberius Caesar there was such a common and almost
universal frenzy for bringing charges of treason, that it took a
heavier toll of the lives of Roman citizens than the whole Civil
War; it seized upon the talk of drunkards, the frank words of
jesters; nothing was safe - anything served as an excuse to shed
blood, and there was no need to wait to find out the fate of the
accused since there was but one outcome. Paulus, a praetorian,
while dining on a certain <Ess3-173>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxvi. 1-xxvii. 3
festive occasion, was wearing a ring with a
conspicuous stone on which the portrait of Tiberius Caesar was
engraved in relief. I should be acting in very silly fashion
if I tried, at this point, to find a polite way of saying that he
took in his hands a chamber-pot - an action that was noticed
simultaneously by Maro, one of the notorious informers of that time,
and by a slave of the victim for whom the trap was being set, who
drew off the ring from the finger of his drunken master. And,
when Maro called the company to witness that the emperor's portrait
had been brought in contact with something foul, and was drawing up
the indictment, the slave showed that the ring was on his own
hand. Whoever calls such a man a slave, will also call Maro a
boon companion!
Under the deified Augustus, it was not yet true that a man's
utterances endangered his life, but they did cause him
trouble. Rufus, a man of senatorial rank, once at a dinner
expressed the hope that Caesar would not return safe from the
journey that he was planning; and he added that all the bulls and
the calves/a wished the same thing. Some of those who were present
carefully noted these words. At the break of day, the slave
who had stood at his feet when he was dining told him what he had
said at dinner while he was drunk, and urged him to be the first to
get Caesar's ear and volunteer charges against himself.
Following this advice, Rufus met Caesar as he was going down to the
forum, and, having sworn that he had been out of his mind the night
before, expressed the hope that his words might recoil upon his own
head and the head of his children, and begged Caesar to pardon him
and restore him to favour. When Caesar had consented to do so,
he said: "No one <Ess3-175>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxvii. 3-xxviii. 3
will believe that you have restored me to
favour unless you bestow upon me a gift," and he asked for a sum
that no favourite need have scorned, and actually obtained it.
"For my own sake," said Caesar, "I shall take pains never to be
angry with you!" Caesar acted nobly in pardoning him and in adding
to his forgiveness liberality. Every one who hears of this
incident must necessarily praise Caesar, but the first to be praised
will be the slave! You need not wait for me to tell you that
the slave who had done this was set free. Yet it was not a
gratuitous act. Caesar had paid the price of his
liberty! After so many instances can there be any doubt that a
master may sometimes receive a benefit from a slave? Why
should a man's condition lessen the value of a service, and the very
value of the service not exalt the man's condition? We all
spring from the same source, {Wyf_of_Bath+} have the same
origin; no man is more noble than another except in so far as the
nature of one man is more upright and more capable of good
actions. Those who display ancestral busts in their halls, and
place in the entrance of their houses the names of their family,
arranged in a long row and entwined in the multiple ramifications of
a genealogical tree - are these not notable rather than noble?
Heaven is the one parent of us all, whether from his earliest origin
each one arrives at his present degree by an illustrious or obscure
line of ancestors. You must not be duped by those who, in
making a review of their ancestors, wherever they find an
illustrious name lacking, foist in the name of a god. Do not
despise any man, even if he belongs with those whose names are
forgotten, and have had too little favour from Fortune. {Wyf_of_Bath+} Whether your line before <Ess3-177>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxviii. 3-xxix. 1
you holds freedmen or slaves or persons of
foreign extraction, boldly lift up your head, and leap over the
obscure names in your pedigree; great nobility awaits you at its
source./a Why are we raised by our pride to such a pitch of vanity
that we scorn to receive benefits from slaves, and, forgetting their
services, look only upon their lot? You who are a slave of
lust, of gluttony, of a harlot - nay, who are the common property of
harlots - do you call any other man a slave? You call any
other man a slave? Whither, pray, are you being rushed by those
bearers who carry around your cushioned litter? Whither are
those fellows in cloaks, tricked out in remarkable livery to look
like soldiers - whither, I say, are these conveying you? To some
door-keeper's door, to the gardens of some slave whose duties are
not even fixed; and then you deny that your own slave is. capable of
giving you a benefit, when in your eyes it is a benefit to have from
another man's slave a kiss? What great inconsistency is
this? At the same time you both despise slaves and court them
- inside your threshold you are imperious and violent, outside
abject, and scorned as greatly as ever you scorn. For none are more
prone to abase themselves than those who are presumptuously puffed
up, and none are more ready to trample upon others than those who
from receiving insults have learned how to give them. {Freedom+} These things needed to
be said in order to crush the arrogance of men who are themselves
dependent upon Fortune, and to claim for slaves the right of
bestowing benefits to the end that it may be claimed also for our
sons. For the question is raised whether children can
sometimes bestow on their <Ess3-179>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxix. 1-5
parents greater benefits than they have
received from them. It is granted me that there have been many
examples of sons who were greater and more powerful than their
parents, and just as freely, too, that they were better men.
If this is true, it is quite possible that they bestowed on them
better gifts, since they were endowed both with greater good fortune
and with better intentions. "However that may be," you reply,
"what a son gives to a father is, in any case, less, because he owes
to his father this very power of giving. So a father is never
surpassed in the matter of a benefit, for the very benefit in which
he is surpassed is really his own." But, in the first
place, there are some things that derive their origin from others,
and yet are greater than their origins; nor is it true that a thing
cannot be greater than that from which it begins on the ground that
it could not have advanced to its great size unless it had had a
beginning. All things exceed by a great degree their origins.
Seeds are the causes of all growing things, and yet are the tiniest
parts of what they produce. Look at the Rhine, look at the
Euphrates, in fact, at all the famous rivers. What are they if
you judge of them from what they are at their source? Whatever
makes them feared, whatever makes them renowned, has been acquired
in their progress. Look at the trunks of trees - the tallest
if you are considering their height, the broadest if you are
considering their thickness and the reach of their branches;
compared with all this, how small a compass the slender thread of
the root embraces! Yet take away the root, and there will be no
springing up of forests, and the mighty moun- <Ess3-181>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxix. 5-xxx. 1
tains will lack their vesture. The
lofty temples of the city rise upon their foundations; yet all that
was thrown down to support their whole structure lies out of
sight. The same is true in the case of all other things;
always their subsequent greatness will conceal their first
beginnings. It would not have been possible for me to attain
anything unless there had been the preceding benefit from my
parents; but it does not follow that whatever I have attained is
inferior to that without which I could not have attained it.
Unless my nurse had suckled me when I was an infant, I should not
have been able to do any of the things that I now perform by brain
and hand nor should I have risen to the present distinction and fame
that my civil and military labours have earned for me; yet, for all
that, surely you will not set more value on the service of my nurse
than on my very weighty achievements? But what difference is
there, since it is just as true that I should not have been able to
advance to my later accomplishments without the benefit from my
nurse as without that from my father? But if I am indebted for
all that I can now do to the source of my being, reflect that the
source of my being is not my father, nor my grandfather, either; for
there will always be something farther removed, from which the
source of a succeeding source is derived. Yet no one will say
that I am more indebted to ancestors that are unknown and have
passed from memory than to my father; I am, however, more indebted,
if the very fact that my father has begotten me is a debt that he
owes to his ancestors. "Whatever I have
bestowed on my father," you say, "even if it is great, falls short
of the value of my <Ess3-183>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxx. 1-4
father's gift to me, for, if he had not
begotten me there would be no gift." Then, too, by this manner of
reasoning, if anyone healed my father when he was sick and about to
die, I shall not be able to bestow on him any benefit that will not
be less than his to me; for my father would not have begotten me if
he had not been healed. But take thought whether it would not
be nearer the truth to count both what I have been able to do, and
what I have done, as something of my own - the product of my own
powers and of my own will. Consider what the fact of my birth
is in itself - a small matter of uncertain character, with a like
potentiality of good and evil, without doubt the first step to
everything else, but not greater than everything else simply because
it comes first. I have saved the life of my father, and raised
him to the highest position; I have made him the chief citizen of
his city, and have not only made him famous by my own achievements,
but also have provided him with a vast and easy opportunity, not
less safe than it is glorious, of achieving something himself; I
have loaded him with honours, with wealth, with everything that
attracts the minds of men, and, although I had place above all
others, I have taken a place below him. Let my father now
say: "The very fact that you have been able to do these things
is a gift from your father," and I shall reply: "Yes, undoubtedly,
if, in order to do all these things, it is only necessary to be
born; but, if the factor that contributes least to successful living
is being alive, and, if you have bestowed on me merely that which I
have in common with wild beasts and some of the tiniest, even some
of the foulest, creatures, then do not take <Ess3-185>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxx. 4-xxxi. 5
credit to yourself for something that does
not arise out of your benefits, even if it does not arise without
them. Suppose that
I have given back life for life. Even in this case I have surpassed
your gift, since I gave to one who was conscious of the gift, and I
was conscious that I was giving it; since, when I gave you your
life, it was not to indulge my own pleasure, or, at any rate, by
means of my own pleasure; since, as it is a lighter thing to die
before one learns to fear death, so it is a greater thing to retain
the breath of life than to receive it. I gave life to one who
would straightway enjoy it, you gave it to one who would not know
whether he was alive; I gave life to one who was afraid of death,
you gave life to me, and made me subject to death; I gave to you
life that was complete and perfect, when you begot me, I was a
creature without reason and a burden to others. Do you wish to know
how small a benefit it is to give life in this way? You should have
exposed me to death as a child; of course by begetting me you did me
a wrong! What, then, is my conclusion? That the fact of
their coition constitutes a very small benefit on the part of a
father and a mother unless they add others which will follow up this
initial gift, and confirm it by still other services. It is
not a blessing to live, but to live well. But you say I do
live well. Yes, but I might also have lived ill; so the only
thing that I have from you is that I am alive. If you claim
credit for giving me mere life, life stripped bare and bereft of
purpose, and boast of it as a great blessing, reflect that you are
claiming credit for giving me a blessing that flies and worms
possess. Finally, though I should mention no more than that I
have <Ess3-187>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxi. 5-xxxii. 4
applied myself to liberal studies, and have
directed the course of my life along the path of rectitude, in the
case of the very benefit I had from you, you have received in return
a greater one than you gave; for you gave to me a self that was
ignorant and inexperienced, and I have given to you a son such as
you might be happy to have begotten. True, my father has
supported me. But, if I bestow the same on him, I return more
than I got, for he has joy, not only from being supported, but from
being supported by a son, and he derives greater pleasure from the
spirit of my act than from the act itself, but the food he gave me
reached only the needs of the body. Tell me, if a man has
attained so much eminence as to be renowned throughout the world by
reason either of his eloquence or of his justice or his military
prowess, if he has been able to encompass his father also in the
greatness of fame, and by the glory of his name to dispel the
obscurity of his birth, has he not conferred upon his parents a
benefit that is beyond all estimate? Or would anyone ever have heard
of Aristo and Gryllus except for the fact that Xenophon and Plato
were their sons? It is Socrates that does not allow the name
of Sophroniscus to die. It would take too long to recount all
the others whose names endure only because they have been handed
down to posterity owing to the exceptional worth of their
children. Which was the greater benefit - what Marcus
Agrippa/a received from his father, who was unknown even after
having had a son like Agrippa, or what the father received from
Agrippa, who, by the glory of a naval crown, gained a distinction
that was unique among the honours of war, who reared in the city so
many mighty works that not only surpassed <Ess3-189>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxii. 5-xxxiii. 1
all former grandeur, but later could be
surpassed by none? Which was the greater benefit - what
Octavius bestowed on his son, or what the deified Augustus bestowed
on his father, obscured as he was by the shadow of an adoptive
father?/a What joy would Octavius have experienced if he had seen
his son, after he had brought the Civil War to an end, watching over
well-established peace: he would not have recognized the good that
he had himself bestowed, and would scarcely have believed, whenever
he turned his gaze backward to himself, that so great a hero could
have been born in his house. Why continue now to mention all
the others who would long have been buried in oblivion, had not the
glory of their sons rescued them from darkness, and kept them in the
light even to this day? Moreover, since the
question is, not what son bestowed greater benefits on his father
than he received from his father, but whether it is possible for any
son to bestow greater benefits, even if the instances that I have
cited are not convincing, and the benefits of parents are not
overtopped by those of their sons, nevertheless that which no age
has as yet produced still lies within the bounds of nature, If
single acts may not be able to surpass the magnitude of a father's
services, yet several of them combined, together will exceed
it. Scipio saved the life of his father in battle,/b and, lad
as he was, spurred his horse into the midst of the enemy. Is
it, then, too small a thing, if, in order to reach his father, he
despised all the dangers, by which at that very time the greatest
leaders were being hard pressed, despised all the difficulties that
blocked his path, if, in order to make his way into the <Ess3-191>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxiii. 1-5
front of the fight, he, tiro that he was,
galloped through the ranks of veterans, if in one bound he
outstripped his years? Then add to this, that he also defended
his father in court, and rescued him from a conspiracy of powerful
enemies, that he heaped upon him a second and a third consulship and
other honours that even consulars might covet, that, when his father
was poor, he handed over to him the wealth that he had seized by
right of war, and made him rich even with the spoils taken from the
enemy, which to a military hero is his greatest glory. If this
is still too little, add that he prolonged his father's
extraordinary powers in his government of the provinces, add that,
after having destroyed the mightiest cities, he, the defender and
founder of the Roman Empire that was destined to reach without a
rival from the rising to the setting sun, added to a hero already
renowned the greater renown of being called the father of
Scipio! Is there any doubt that the commonplace benefit of his
birth was surpassed by his rare filial devotion and his valour,
which brought to the city itself, I might almost say, greater glory
than protection? Then, if this is still too little, imagine
some son that rescued his father from tortures, imagine that he
transferred them to himself. You may extend the benefits of a
son to any length you please, whereas the gift of a father is of one
sort only, easily given, and fraught with pleasure to the giver -
one that he must necessarily have given to many others, even to some
to whom he does not know that he gave it, one in which he has a
partner, in which he has had regard for the law, his country, the
rewards that accrue to fathers, the continuance of his house and
family, for everything, in fact, but the recipient of his
gift. Tell me, <Ess3-193>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxiii. 5-xxxv. 2
if a son has attained the wisdom of
philosophy and has transmitted it to his father, shall we still be
able to argue as to whether he gave something greater than he
received, though the gift he returned to his father was the Happy
life,/a and that which he received was merely life? xxx"But," you
say, "whatever you do, whatever you are able to bestow on your
father, is a part of his benefit to you." Yes, and the progress I
have made in liberal studies is a benefit from my teacher;
nevertheless we leave behind the very teachers who bave transmitted
their knowledge, particularly those who have taught us the alphabet,
and, although no one could have accomplished anything without them,
it is, nevertheless, not true that, no matter how much anyone has
accomplished, he is still their inferior. There is a great
deal of difference between what is first in time and what is first
in importance, and it does not follow that what is first in time is
the equivalent of what is first in importance on the ground that
without the first in time there could be no first in importance. It is now time to
produce something coined, so to speak, in the Stoic mint./b He who
has given a benefit that falls short of being the best faces the
possibility of being outdone. A father has given life to his
son, but there is something better than life; so the father can be
outdone because he has given a benefit that falls short of being the
best. Again, if a man who has given life to another has been
freed, time and again, from the peril of death, he has received a
greater benefit than he gave. Now, a father has given life;
if, therefore, he should be repeatedly freed from the peril of death
by his son, it is possible <Ess3-195>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxv. 3-xxxvi. 1
for him to receive a greater benefit than he
gave. The more need a man has of a benefit, the greater is the
benefit he receives. Now, one who is alive has more need of
life than one who has not been born, since such a one can feel no
need at all; consequently, if a father has received life from his
son, he has received a greater benefit from the son than the son
received from his father by being born. "Benefits from a
father," you say, "canot be surpassed by benefits from a son.
And why ? Because the son received life from his father, and,
unless he had received it, he could not have given any benefits at
all." But a father has this in common with all men who have at any
time given life to others; for these would not have been able to
return gratitude unless they had received the gift of their lives.
Consequently, you cannot return too much gratitude to a physician
(for physicians also habitually give life), nor to a sailor if he
has rescued you from shipwreck. Yet the benefits of these and
of others, who have in some fashion given us life, are capable of
being surpassed; therefore those of a father also are capable of
it. If anyone has given to me the sort of benefit that needs
to be supplemented by benefits from many others, while I have given
to him the benefit that needs a supplement from no man, then I have
given a greater one than I have received. Now a father gave to
his son a life which, unless it had had many accessories that
preserved it, would have perished; whereas a son, if he has given
life to his father, gave that which needed the help of no man to
make it endure; therefore a father who received his life from a son
received a greater benefit than he himself gave. These
considerations do not destroy respect for <Ess3-197>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxvi. 1-xxxviii. 1
parents, nor render children worse than
their parents, but even better; for by its very nature Virtue loves
to shine, and is eager to push ahead of any in front. Filial
devotion will be all the more ardent if it approaches the repayment
of benefits with the hope of surpassing them. And the fathers
themselves will be willing and glad to have it happen since, in the
case of a great many things, it is to our advantage to be
surpassed. How else comes a rivalry so desirable? How
else comes to parents a happiness so great that, in the matter of
benefits, they acknowledge themselves to be no match for their
children? Unless we adopt this view of the matter, we supply
children with an excuse, and make them less ready to return
gratitude, whereas we ought to spur them on and say to them: "To your task, young
heroes! A glorious contest is set before you - the contest
between parents and children to decide whether they have given, or
received, the greater benefits. Your fathers have not won the
victory for the mere reason that they were first on the field.
Only show the spirit that befits you, and do not lose courage - they
desire to have you win. Nor, in this glorious struggle, will
there be any lack of leaders to encourage you to do as they did, and
bid you follow their footsteps to the victory that often ere now has
been won from parents. "Aeneas won the
victory from his father; for, though he himself, in his infancy, had
been but a light and safe burden to his father's arms, he bore his
father, heavy with years, through the midst of the lines of the
enemy, through the destruction of the city that was crashing around
him, while the pious old man, clasping in his arms his sacred relics
and household gods <Ess3-199>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxvii. 1-4
burdened his son's progress with more than
his simple weight; he bore him through flames, and (what cannot
filial love accomplish!) bore him out of danger,/a and placed him,
for our worship, among the founders of the Roman Empire. "Those young
Sicilians/b won the victory; for, when Aetna, aroused to unusual
fury, poured forth its fire upon cities, upon fields, upon a great
part of the island, they conveyed their parents to safety. The
fires parted, so it was believed, and, as the flames retired on
either side, a path was opened up for the passage of the youths, who
greatly deserved to perform their heroic tasks in safety. "Antigonus won the
victory; for, having vanquished the enemy in a mighty battle, he
transferred to his father the prize of the war, and handed over to
him the sovereignty of Cyprus. This is true kingship, to
refuse to be king when you might have been. "Manlius won the
victory from his father, tyrant though he was; for, although his
father had previously banished him for a time because of his
dullness and stupidity as a youth, he went to the tribune of the
people, who had appointed a day for his father's trial; having asked
for an interview, which the tribune granted, expecting to find him a
traitor to his detested father - he believed, too, that he had
earned the gratitude of the young man, for, among other charges that
he was bringing against Manlius, the gravest was his son's exile -
the youth, when he had obtained his private audience, drew forth a
sword, that he had had concealed beneath his robe, and cried:
'Unless you swear that you will remit the charges against my father,
I shall run you through <Ess3-201>
ON BENEFITS, III. xxxvii. 4-xxxviii. 3
with this sword. It lies with you to
decide which way my father shall have of escaping his accuser.' The
tribune took the oath and did not break it, and he reported to the
assembly his reason for abandoning the action. No other man was ever
permitted to put a tribune in his place without being
punished. "There are countless instances of others who have
snatched their parents from dangers, who have advanced them from the
lowest to the highest station, and, taking them from the nameless
mass of commoners, have given them a name that will sound throughout
the ages. No power of words, no wealth of genius can express
how great, how laudable, how sure of living in the memory of men
will be the achievement of being able to say: 'I obeyed my parents,
I gave way to their authority, whether it was just or unjust and
harsh, I showed myself humble and submissive; in only one thing was
I stubborn - the resolve not to be outdone by them in benefits.'
Struggle on, I beg of you, and, even though wearied, renew the
fight. Happy they who shall conquer, happy they who shall be
conquered. What can be more glorious than the youth who can
say to himself (for to say it to another would be an impiety): 'I
have surpassed my father in benefits'? What can be more
fortunate than the old man who, to all ears and in all places, will
declare that in benefits he has been surpassed by his son? But
what can be happier than to lose that victory?
<Ess3-203>
BOOK IV
OF all the questions that we have discussed,
Aebutius Liberalis, none can seem so essential, or to need, as
Sallust puts it, such careful treatment, as the one that is now
before us - whether to bestow a benefit and to return gratitude for
it are in themselves desirable ends. Some are to be found
who cultivate honourable practices for the recompense, and care
nothing for virtue that is unrewarded; whereas it has nothing
glorious in it if it shows any element of profit. For what is more
shameful than for anyone to calculate the value to a man of being
good, since Virtue neither invites by the prospect of gain, nor
deters by the prospect of loss, and, so far is she from bribing any
man with hopes and promises, that, on the contrary, she bids him
spend upon her, and is more often found in voluntary
contributions. We must go to her, trampling under foot all
self-interest; whithersoever she calls, whithersoever she sends us
we must go, without any regard for our fortunes, sometimes even
without sparing our own blood, and we must never refuse her demands.
"And what shall I gain," you ask, "if I do this bravely, if I do it
gladly?" Only the gain of having done it - she promises you nothing
besides. If you should chance to encounter some profit, count
it as something additional. The <Ess3-205>
ON BENEFITS, IV. i. 3-ii. 4
reward of virtuous acts lies in the acts
themselves. If a virtuous act is in itself a desirable end,
if, further, a benefit is a virtuous act, it follows that, since
they bear the same nature, they cannot be subject to a different
condition. But that the virtuous course is in itself a
desirable end has been often and abundantly proved. On this point we
Stoics are in arms against the Epicureans, an effeminate,
sheltered/a set, who philosophize over their cups, and hold that
Virtue is but the handmaid of Pleasures, that she obeys them, that
she is their slave, and sees them enthroned above herself.
"There can be no pleasure," you say, "without virtue." But why does
it come before virtue? Do you suppose that the question is one
of mere precedence? The whole principle and power f virtue are
thrown into doubt. Virtue does not exist if it is possible for
her to follow; hers is the first place, she must lead, must command,
must have the supreme position; you bid her ask for the
watchword! "What difference," you say, "does it make?
Even I affirm that there can be no happy life without virtue.
The very pleasure at which I aim, to which I am enslaved,{freedom+} I disapprove of and condemn if
she is banished. The only point in question is whether virtue
is the cause of the highest good, or is itself the highest good." Do
you suppose that the answer to this question turns upon merely
making a shift in the order? It does indeed show confusion and
obvious blindness to give preference to last things over first
things. But what I protest against is, not that virtue is
placed second to pleasure, but that virtue is associated with
pleasure at all, for virtue despises pleasure, is its enemy, and
recoils from it as far as it <Ess3-207>
ON BENEFITS, IV. ii. 4-iii. 3
can, being more acquainted with labour and
sorrow, which are manly ills, than with this womanish good of yours.
It has been
needful, my Liberalis, to introduce these considerations here,
because the bestowal of the kind of benefit that is now under
discussion is a mark of virtue, and to bestow it for any reason
other than the mere bestowing of it is a most shameful act. For, if
we made contributions with the expectation of receiving a return, we
should give, not to the most worthy, but to the richest, men; as it
is, we prefer a poor man to an importunate rich man. That is
not a benefit which has regard for the fortune of the
recipient. Moreover, if it were only self- interest that moved
us to help others, those who could most easily dispense benefits,
such as the rich and powerful and kings, who need no help from
others, would not be under the least obligation to bestow them; nor,
indeed, would the gods bestow the countless gifts that, day and
night, they unceasingly pour forth, for their own nature is
sufficient to them for all their needs, and renders them fully
provided and safe and inviolable; they will, therefore, give to no
man a benefit if their only motive in bestowing it is a regard for
themselves and their own advantage. To take thought, not where you
can best place your benefit, but where you can derive the most gain,
and from whom you can most readily collect, is to be, not a
benefactor, but a money-lender. And, since the gods are far
removed from such concern, it follows that they will not be liberal;
for, if the only reason for giving a benefit is the advantage of the
giver, and if God can hope for no advantage from us, then no motive
is found for God's giving a benefit. <Ess3-209>
ON BENEFITS, IV. iv. 1-v. 1 I know the
answer that can be made to this: "Yes, and therefore God does
not give benefits, but, free from all care and unconcerned about us,
he turns his back on the world, and either does something else, or -
that which Epicurus counts supreme happiness - does nothing at all,
and benefits no more concern him than injuries." But he who says
this does not hearken to the voices of those who pray and of those
who all around him, lifting their hands to heaven, offer vows for
blessings public and private. Assuredly this would not be the
case, assuredly all mortals would not have agreed upon this madness
of addressing divinities that were deaf and gods that were
ineffectual, unless we were conscious of their benefits that
sometimes are presented unasked, sometimes are granted in answer to
prayer - great and timely gifts, which by their coming remove grave
menaces. And who is so wretched, so uncared for, who has been
born to so cruel a destiny and punishment as never to have
experienced the great bounty of the gods? Look at those who
bemoan and deplore their lot - you will find that even these are not
wholly excluded from heavenly benefits, that there is not one to
whom some benefit has not trickled from that most bountiful
spring. And the gift that at birth is dispensed equally to all
- is this too small a thing? Though the fortunes to which we
pass in later life are dispensed in unequal measure, was it too
small a thing that Nature gave when she gave to us herself?
"God gives no benefits," you say. Whence, then, comes all that
you possess, all that you give, all that you withhold, all that you
hoard, all that you steal? Whence come the countless things
that delight your <Ess3-211>
ON BENEFITS, IV. v. i-vi. i
eyes, your ears, your mind? Whence the
profusion that supplies even our luxury? For it is not merely
our necessities that are provided - we are loved to the point of
being spoiled! Whence all the trees yielding their varied
fruits, all the healing plants, all the different sorts of foods
distributed throughout the whole year, so that even the slothful
find sustenance from the chance produce of the earth? Whence,
too, the living creatures of every kind, some born upon dry and
solid ground, others in the waves, others that descend through the
air, in order that every part of Nature's domain might pay to us
some tribute? Whence the rivers - these that encircle the
fields in loveliest curves, those that, as they flow on in their
vast and navigable courses, provide a channel for commerce, some of
which in the days of summer undergo a wonderful increase in size in
order that, by the sudden overflow of the summer torrent, they may
water the parched lands that lie outstretched beneath a burning
sky? And what of the springs of healing waters? What of
the warm waters that bubble forth upon the very coast of the sea?
And thee, O lordly Larius,
and, Benacus, thee, Rising with a roar
of billows like the sea?/a If anyone had made vou a gift
of but a few acres, you would say that you had received a benefit;
and do you say that the illimitable stretches that the earth opens
to you are not a benefit? If anyone has presented you with
money, and, since this is a great thing in your eyes, has filled
your coffer, you will call it a benefit. God has planted in
the earth countless mines, has drawn forth from its depths countless
rivers that over the lands where they flow carry down
<Ess3-213>
ON BENEFITS, IV. vi. 1-4
gold; silver and copper and iron in huge
store have been buried in all places, and he has given to you the
means of discovering them by placing upon the surface of the earth
the signs of its hidden treasures yet do you say that you have
received no benefit? If you should receive the gift of a house
that was resplendent with marble and a ceiling gleaming with gold or
decked out with colours, you would call it no commonplace gift. God
has built for you a huge mansion that need not fear conflagration or
ruin, a house in which you see, not flimsy veneers/a thinner than
the very blade by which they are sawn, but virgin masses of most
precious stone, whole masses of a substance with such a variety of
markings that the tiniest fragments of it fill you with wonder, and
a ceiling gleaming in one fashion by night, and in another by day -
yet do you say that you have received no gift? And, though you
prize greatly these blessings that you possess, do you act the part
of an ungrateful man, and consider that you are indebted to no one
for them? Whence do you have that breath which you draw?
Whence that light by which you distribute and order the acts of your
life? Whence the blood that by its circulation maintains the
heat of life? Whence those dainties that by rare flavours
excite your palate when it is already sated? Whence those
provocatives of pleasure when it palls? Whence this repose in
which you wither and rot? Will you not, if you are grateful,
say i.e., of marble. <Ess3-215>
ON BENEFITS, IV. vi. 4-vii. 1
A god for us this ease hath
wrought. For he Shall ever be a god
indeed to me, And many a firstling lamb
his altar stain From out our flock. You see what boons I
gain My oxen by his bounty roam at will,
While I fond
airs upon my pipe can trill?/a <Virg.Ecl>
But God is he who has
set free, not a few oxen, but herds throughout the whole earth, who
everywhere supplies food to the flocks as they range far and wide,
who after pastures of summer has provided pastures of winter, who
has not merely taught how to play upon the pipe and to fashion a
tune that, rustic and artless as it is, yet shows some regard for
form, but has invented countless arts, the countless variations of
the voice, the countless tones that will produce melodies, some by
the breath of our body, others by the breath of an instrument./b For
you must not say that whatever we have invented is our own any more
than the fact of our growth, or the fact that the behaviour of our
body corresponds with the fixed, periods of life; now comes the loss
of childhood's teeth, now, as age gradually advances and passes into
the hardier stage, puberty and the last tooth that marks the end of
the progress of youth. In us are implanted the seeds of all ages,
the seeds of all the arts, and it is God, our master, who draws
forth from the secret depths of our being our various talents.
"It is Nature," you say, "who supplies me with these things." But do
you not understand that, when you say this, you merely give another
name to to God? For what else is Natuure but God and the
Divine Reason that pervades the whole universe and all its
parts? {Wordsworth+} You may, as
often as you like, address this being who is the author of this
world of ours by <Ess3-217>
ON BENEFITS, IV. vii. I-vill. 3
different names; it will be right for you to
call him Jupiter Best and Greatest, and the Thunderer and the
Stayer, a title derived, not from the fact that, as the historians
have related, the Roman battle-line stayed its flight in answer to
prayer,/a but from the fact that all things are stayed by his
benefits, that he is their Stayer and Stabilizer. If likewise
you should call him Fate, it would be no falsehood; for, since Fate
is nothing but a connected chain of causes, he is the first of all
the causes on which the others depend. Any name that you
choose will be properly applied to him if it connotes some force
that operates in the domain of heaven - his titles may be as
countless as are his benefits. Our school regard him
both as Father Liber and as Hercules and as Mercury -Father Liber,
because he is the father of all things, he who first discovered the
seminal power that is able to subserve life through pleasure;
Hercules, because his power is invincible, and, whenever it shall
have grown weary with fulfilling its works, shall return into primal
fire/b; Mercury, because to him belong reason and number and order
and knowledge. In whatever direction you turn, you will see
God coming to meet you; nothing is void of him, he himself fills all
his work. {Wordsworth+} For this reason, O most
ungrateful of mortals, it is futile for you to say that you are
indebted, not to God, but to Nature, for there is no Nature without
God, nor God without Nature, but both are the same thing, they
differ only in their function. If, having received a gift from
Seneca, you were to say that you were indebted to Annaeus or to
Lucius,c you would be changing, not your creditor, but his name,
for, whether you designated him by his first, his second, <Ess3-219>
ON BENEFITS, IV. viii. 3-ix. 3
or his third name, he would nevertheless be
the same person. So, if you like, speak of Nature, Fate,
Fortune, but all these are names of the same God, who uses his power
in various ways. And justice, honesty,/a prudence, courage,
temperance are the good qualities of only one mind; if you take
pleasure in any of these, you take pleasure in that mind. But, not to be drawn
aside into further controversy, God bestows upon us very many and
very great benefits, with no thought of any return, since he has no
need of having anything bestowed, nor are we capable of bestowing
anything on him; consequently, a benefit is something that is
desirable in itself. It has in view only the advantage of the
recipient; so, putting aside all interests of our own, let us aim
solely at this. xxx"Yet you say," someone retorts, "that we ought to
take care to select those to whom we would give benefits, since even
the farmer does not commit his seeds to sand; but if this is true,
then in giving benefits we are seeking our own advantage, just as
surely as in ploughing and sowing; for sowing is not something that
is desirable in itself. Moreover, you inquire where and how
you should bestow a benefit, which there would be no need of doing
if giving a benefit is something that is desirable in itself, since,
in whatever place and in whatever fashion it was bestowed, it would
still be a benefit." But we pursue honour solely for its own sake;
yet, even if we should have no other reason for pursuing it, we do
inquire what we should do and when and how we should do it; for it
is just through these considerations that honour has its
being. And so, when I select the person to whom I would give a
benefit, I am thinking <Ess3-221>
ON BENEFITS, IV. ix. 3-x. 5
of this - how and when a gift is a benefit;
for if it is given to one who is base, it can be neither an
honourable act nor a benefit. To restore a deposit
is something that is desirable in itself; yet I shall not always
restore it, nor at every time or in every place. Sometimes it
is a matter of indifference whether I deny a deposit or restore it
openly. I shall always regard the interest of the one to whom
I am intending to restore a deposit, and shall refuse to do so if it
will do him harm. I shall proceed in the same way in the
matter of a benefit. I shall consider when to give it, to whom
to give it, and how and why. For reason should be applied to
everything we do and no gift can be a benefit unless it is given
with reason, since every virtuous act is accompanied by
reason. How often, when men are reproaching themselves for
some thoughtless benefaction, do we hear the words : "I would
rather have lost it than have given it to him"! Thoughtless
benefaction is the most shameful sort of loss, and it is a much
greater offence to have ill bestowed a benefit than to have received
no return; for it is the fault of another if we have received no
return, while, if we did not select the one to whom we were giving,
the fault is our own. In making my choice no considerations
will influence me so little as the one you suppose - who will be
likely to make me some return; for I choose a person who will be
grateful, not one who is likely to make a return, and it often
happens that the grateful man is one who is not likely to make a
return, while the ungrateful man is one who has made a return.
It is to the heart that my estimate is directed; consequently I
shall pass by the man who, though rich, is unworthy, and shall <Ess3-223>
ON BENEFITS, IV. x. 5-xi. 3
give to one who, though poor, is good; for
he will be grateful in the midst of extreme poverty, and, when he
lacks all else, this heart he will still have. It is not gain
that I try to get from a benefit, nor pleasure, nor glory; content
with giving pleasure to one human being, I shall give with the
single purpose of doing what I ought. But I am not without
choice in doing what I ought. Do you ask what the nature of
this choice will be I shall choose a man who is upright, sincere,
mindful, grateful, {integrum+} {simplicem+} {memorem+} {gratum+} keeps
his hands from another man's property, who is not greedily attached
to his own, who is kind to others; although Fortune may bestow upon
him nothing with which be may repay my favour, I shall have
accomplished my purpose when I have made choice of such a man.
If I am made liberal by self-interest and mean calculation, if my
only purpose in doing a service to a man is to have him in turn do a
service to me, I shall not give a benefit to one who is setting out
for distant and foreign countries, never to return; I shall not give
to one who is so ill that he has no hope of recovery; I shall not
give when my own health is failing, for I shall have no time to
receive a return. And yet, that you may know that generous
action is something desirable in itself, the foreigner who has just
put into our harbour, and will straightway depart, receives our
assistance; to a shipwrecked stranger, in order that he may sail
back home, we both give a ship and equip it. He leaves us
scarcely knowing who was the author of his salvation, and, expecting
never more to see our faces again, he deputes the gods to be our
debtors, and prays that they may repay the favour in his stead;
meanwhile we rejoice in the consciousness of having given a <Ess3-225>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xi. 4-xii. 1
benefit that will yield no fruit. And
tell me, when we have reached the very end of life, and are drawing
up our will, do we not dispense benefits that will yield us
nothing? How much time is spent, how long do we debate with
ourselves to whom and how much we shall give! For what
difference does it make to whom we give since no one will make us
any return? Yet never are we more careful in our giving, never
do we wrestle more in making decisions than when, with all
self-interest banished, only the ideal of good remains before our
eyes; we are bad judges of our duties only so long as they are
distorted by hope and fear and that most slothful of vices,{Hal+} pleasure. But when death has
shut off all these, and has brought us to pronounce sentence as
incorrupt judges, we search for those who are most worthy to inherit
our possessions, and there is nothing that we arrange with more
scrupulous care than this which is of no concern to ourselves. Yet,
heavens! the great joy that comes to us as we think: "Through
me this man will become richer, and I, by increasing his wealth,
shall add new lustre to his high position." If we give only when we
may expect some return, we ought to die intestate! "You say," someone
retorts, "a benefit is a loan that cannot be repaid; but a loan is
not something that is desirable in itself." {Polonius+}
When I use the term "loan," I resort to a figure, a metaphor; for in
the same way I can also say that a law is the measure of justice and
injustice, and a measure is not something desirable in itself. We
resort to such terms for the purpose of making something clear; when
I say a "loan," a quasi-loan is understood. Do you wish to
know the difference? I add the words "that <Ess3-227>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xii. 1-4
cannot be repaid," whereas every true loan
either can or ought to be repaid. So far from its being right
for us to give a benefit from a motive of self-interest, often, as I
have said, the giving of it must involve one's own loss and
risk. For instance, I come to the rescue of a man who has been
surrounded by robbers although I am at liberty to pass by in safety.
By defending an accused man, who is battling with privilege, I turn
against.myself a clique of powerful men, and shall be forced perhaps
by the same accusers to put on the mourning that I have removed from
him, although I might take the other side, and look on in safety at
struggles that do not concern me; I go bail for a man who has been
condemned, and, when a friend's goods are put up for sale, I quash
the indictment, and shall probably make myself responsible for what
he owes to his creditors; in order to save a proscribed person, I
myself run the risk of proscription. No one, when he wishes
to acquire an estate at Tusculum or at Tibur because of their
healthfulness and the retreat they afford in summer, stops to
consider at how many years' purchase/b he is going to buy; when once
he has bought/c it, he must look after it. In the case of a benefit
the same principle applies; for, when you ask me what the return
will be, I answer, "the reward of a good conscience." What return
does one have from a benefit? Do you, pray, tell me what
return one has from justice, from innocence, from greatness of
soul, {magnitudo_animi+} from chastity, from
temperance; if you seek for anything besides the <Ess3-229>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xii. 5-xiii. 3
virtues themselves, it is not the virtues
themselves that you seek. To what end does heaven perform its
revolutions? To what end does the sun lengthen and shorten the
day? These are all benefits, for they take place in order to
work good to us. Just as it is the office of heaven to perform
its revolutions in the fixed order of Nature, and that of the sun to
shift the points at which it rises and sets, and to do these things
that are serviceable to us without any reward, so it is the duty of
man, amongst other things, to give also benefits. Why, then,
does he give? For fear that he should fail to give, for fear
that he should lose an opportunity of doing good. {giving_motive+} You count it pleasure to
surrender your miserable body to sluggish ease, to court a repose
that differs not much from sleep, to lurk in a covert of thick shade
and beguile the lethargy of a languid mind with the most delicate
thoughts, which you call tranquillity, and in the secret retreats of
your gardens to stuff with food and drink your bodies that are
pallid from inaction; we count it pleasure to give benefits, even at
the price of labour, if only they will lighten the labours of
others, even at the price of danger, if only they will extricate
others from dangers, even at the expense of burdening our budgets,
if only they will relieve the needs and distresses of others.
What difference does it make whether my benefits are returned?
Even after they have been returned, they must be given again.
A benefit views the interest, not of ourselves, but of the one upon
whom it is bestowed; otherwise, it is to ourselves that we give
it. And so many services that confer the utmost advantage on
others lose claim to gratitude because they are paid for. The
trader renders service to <Ess3-231>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xiii. 3-xiv. 4
cities, the physician to the sick, the
slave-monger to those he sells; but all these, because they arrive
at the good of others through seeking their own, do not leave those
whom they serve under any obligation. That which has gain as
its object cannot be a benefit. "I shall give so much and get
so much in return " is pure barter. I should not call that
woman chaste who repulses a lover in order to inflame him, who is
afraid either of the law or of her husband. As Ovid puts it:/a
She who sinned not because she
could not - sinned. A woman who owes her chastity, not
to herself, but to fear, is very rightly put in the class of
sinners. In the same way, he who has given a benefit in order
that he may get something back has really not given it. At
this rate, we also give a benefit to the animals that we rear in
order that they may provide us either with service or with
food! We give a benefit to the orchards that we tend in order
that they may not suffer from drought or the hardness of untilled
and neglected ground. But it is not justice nor goodness that
moves anyone to cultivate a field, or to perform any act that
involves some reward apart from the act itself. The motive
that leads to the giving of a benefit is not greedy nor mean, but is
humane and generous, a desire to give even when one has already
given, and to add new and fresh gifts to old ones, having as its
sole aim the working of as much good as it can for him upon whom it
bestows; whereas it is a contemptible act, without praise and
without glory, to do anyone a service because it is to our own
interest. What nobleness is there in loving oneself, in
sparing oneself, in getting gain for oneself? The true desire
<Ess3-233>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xiv. 4-xv. 4
of giving a benefit summons us away from all
these motives, and, laying hand upon us, forces us to put up with
loss, and, forgoing self-interest, finds its greatest joy in the
mere act of doing good. Can there be any doubt
that the opposite of a benefit is an injury? Just as doing an
injury is something that in itself must be avoided and shunned, so
giving a benefit is something that is desirable in itself. In
one case, the baseness of the action outweighs all the rewards that
urge us to the crime, in the other, we are incited to the action by
the idea of virtue, which is in itself a powerful incentive. I
shall not be guilty of misstatement if I say that everyone takes
delight in the benefits he does, that everyone is so disposed that
he is made more happy by seeing the one upon whom he has heaped
benefits, that everyone finds in the fact of having given one
benefit a reason for giving a second one. And this would not
happen if the benefits themselves were not the source of his
pleasure. How often will you hear a man say: "I cannot
bear to desert him, for I have given him his life, I have rescued
him from peril. He now begs me to plead his cause against men
of influence; I do not want to, but what can I do? I have
already helped him once, no, twice." Do you not see that there is,
inherent in the thing itself, some peculiar power that compels us to
give benefits, first, because we ought, then, because we have
already given them? Though in the beginning we may have had no
reason for bestowing anything upon a man, we continue to bestow
because we have already bestowed; and so untrue is it that we are
moved to give benefits from a motive of profit, that we persist in
maintaining and cherishing those that are unprofitable, solely from
an <Ess3-235>
ON BENEFITS, IV, xv. 4-xvii. 1
affection for the benefit, to which, even
though it has been unfortunately placed, we show indulgence as
naturally as we might to children who misbehave. These same
opponents a admit that they themselves return gratitude, yet not
because it is right, but because it is expedient. But to prove
that this is false is an easier task, because the same arguments by
which we have established that to give a benefit is something that
is desirable in itself establish this also. The one fixed
principle from which we proceed to the proof of other points is that
the honourable is cherished for no other reason than because it is
honourable+. Who, therefore, will dare to raise the question
whether it is honourable to be grateful? Who does not loathe
the ungrateful man, a person who is unprofitable even to himself?
And tell me, when you hear it said of someone: "He is
ungrateful for very great benefits," what are your feelings?
Is it as though he had done something base, or as though he had
omitted to do something that was expedient and likely to be
profitable to himself? I imagine you count him a worthless
fellow, who should have, not a guardian, but punishment; but this
would not be the case unless to be grateful were something that is
desirable in itself and honourable. Other qualities, perhaps,
manifest their worth less clearly, and, in order to decide whether
they are honourable, we need an interpreter. This one is open
to the view, and is too beautiful to have its glory dimmed or
obscured. What is so praiseworthy, upon what are all our minds
so uniformly agreed, as the repayment of good services with
gratitude? Tell me, what is the motive that leads to this?
Gain? But he who does not scorn gain is ungrateful. <Ess3-237>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xvii. 1-4
Vainglory? And what is there to boast
about in having paid what you owe? Fear? The ungrateful
man has none; for this is the only crime for which we have provided
no law, on the theory that Nature has taken sufficient precautions
against it. Just as there is no law that bids us love our
parents or indulge our children, for it is useless to push us in the
direction in which we are already going, just as no one needs to be
urged to self- love, which seizes him even while he is being born,
so, too, there is none for this, no law that bids us seek the
honourable in and for itself; it pleases us by its very nature, and
so attractive is virtue that even the wicked instinctively approve
of the better course./a Who is there who does not wish to seem
beneficent? who,even in the midst of his crimes and injuries, does
not aspire to a reputation for goodness? who does not clothe even
his most violent acts with some semblance of righteousness, and wish
to have the appearance of having given a benefit even to those whom
he has injured? {evil_as_good+}
And so men suffer those whom they have ruined to render them thanks,
and they make a pretence of being good and generous because they are
not able to, prove themselves so. But they would not do this
unless the love of what is right and desirable in itself forced them
to seek a reputation at variance with their characters, and conceal
the wickedness, which they regard with hatred and shame, while they
covet its fruits; no one has ever so far revolted from Nature's law
and put aside humanity as to be evil for the pleasure of it. {Iago+} For ask any of the men who live by
robbery whether they would not prefer to attain by honourable means
the things that they get by brigandage and theft. The man who
gets his living by highway robbery and <Ess3-239>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xvii. 4-xviii. 3
by murdering travellers will desire rather
to find his booty than to snatch it; you will discover no one who
would not prefer to enjoy the rewards of wickedness without the
wickedness. Of all the benefits that we have from Nature this
is the greatest, the fact that Virtue causes her light to penetrate
into the minds of all; even those who do not follow her see her. To prove to you that
the sentiment of gratitude is something to be desired in itself,
ingratitude is something to be avoided in itself because there is
nothing that so effectually disrupts and destroys the harmony of the
human race as this vice. For how else do we live in security
if it is not that we help each other by an exchange of good offices?
It is only through the interchange of benefits that life becomes in
some measure equipped and fortified against sudden disasters.
Take us singly, and what are we? The prey of all creatures,
their victims, whose blood is most delectable and most easily
secured. For, while other creatures possess a strength that is
adequate for their self-protection, and those that are born to be
wanderers and to lead an isolated life have been given weapons, the
covering of man is a frail skin; no might of claws or of teeth makes
him a terror to others, naked and weak as he is, his safety lies in
fellowship. {social_animal+} God has given to him
two things, reason and fellowship, which, from being a creature at
the mercy of others, make him the most powerful of all; and so he
who, if he were isolated, could be a match for none is the master of
the world. Fellowship has given to him dominion over all
creatures; fellowship, though he was begotten upon the land, has
extended his sovereignty to an element not his own, and has bidden
him be lord even upon the sea; it is this that has <Ess3-241>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xviii. 3-xix. 4
checked the assaults of disease, has made
ready supports for old age, has provided solace for sorrow; it is
this that makes us brave, this that we may invoke as a help against
Fortune. Take away this fellowship, and you will sever the
unity of the human race on which its very existence depends; yet you
will take it away if you succeed in proving that ingratitude is to
be avoided, not because of itself, but because it has something to
fear; for how many there are who might safely be ungrateful!
In fine, any man who is made grateful by fear I call ungrateful. No sane man fears the
gods; for it is madness to fear what is beneficial, and no one loves
those whom he fears. You, Epicurus, in the end leave God
unarmed, you have stripped him of all his weapons, of all his power,
and, in order that no one may have need to fear him, you have thrust
him beyond the range of fear. Surrounded, therefore, as he is,
by a vast and impassable wall, and removed beyond the reach and
sight of mortals, you have no reason to stand in awe of him; he has
no means of bestowing either blessing or injury; in the space that
separates our own from some other heaven a he dwells alone, without
a living creature, without a human being, without a possession, and
avoids the destruction of the worlds that crash around and above
him, having no ear for our prayers and no concern for us. And
yet you wish to seem to worship this being, from a feeling of
gratitude, I suppose, as if he were a father; or, if you do not wish
to seem grateful, because you have from him not a single benefit,
but are yourself merely a combination of atoms/b and of those mites
of yours that have met blindly and by chance, why do you worship
him? "Because of his glorious majesty," <Ess3-243>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xlx. 4-xx. 3
you say and his exceptional nature."
Granting that you do this, you clearly do it without the inducement
of any reward, of any expectation; there is, therefore, something
that is desirable in itself, whose very worth induces you, that is,
the honourable. {honestum+} But what is more
honourable than gratitude? The opportunity for this virtue is
limited only by life. "Bnbsp; "But this good," you say, "has in it
also some element of profit." What virtue, indeed, has not?
But that is said to be desired because of itself which, although it
possesses some outside advantages, still pleases even when these
have been stripped of and removed. There is advantage in being
grateful; yet I shall be grateful even if it harms me. And
what is the aim of one who is grateful? Is it that his
gratitude may win for him more friends, more benefits? What,
then, if a man is likely to arouse disfavour by it, if a man knows
that, so far from being likely to gain anything by it, he must lose
much from the store that he has already acquired, does he not gladly
submit to his losses? He is ungrateful who in the act of
repaying gratitude has an eye on a second gift -who hopes while he
repays. I call him ungrateful who sits at the bedside of a sick man
because he is going to make his will, who finds room for an thought
of an inheritance or a legacy. Though he should do everything
that a good and thoughtful friend ought to do, if his mind is
haunted by the hope of gain, he is only a fisher for legacies an is
just dropping his hook. As birds of prey that feed upon
carcasses keep watch near by the flocks that are spent with disease
and are ready to drop, so such a man gloats over a death-bed and
hovers about the corpse. <Ess3-245>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxi. 1-4
But the grateful heart is
attracted by the very excellence of its purpose. Do you wish
proof that this is so, and that it is not corrupted by the idea of
profit? There are two classes of grateful men. One man
is said to be grateful because he has made return for something that
he received; he, perhaps,is able to make himself conspicuous, has
something to boast about, something to publish. He, too, is
said to be grateful who has accepted a benefit in good spirit, who
owes in good spirit; this man keeps his gratitude shut up in his
heart. What profit can he gain from this hidden feeling? Yet
such a man, even if he is able to do no more than this, is grateful.
He loves, is conscious of his debt, desires to repay the favour;
whatever else you may find wanting, nothing is wanting in the man
himself. A man may be an artist even if he does not have at
hand the tools for practising his craft, nor is one less a trained
singer if the noise of those who are crying him down does not permit
his voice to be heard. I wish to repay a favour: after this
something is left for me to do, not in order to become grateful, but
in order to become free/a; for it often happens that he who has
repaid a favour is ungrateful, and he who has not repaid it is
grateful. For, as in the case of all the others, the true estimate
of this virtue is concerned wholly with the heart; if this does its
duty, whatever else is lacking is the fault of Fortune. Just
as a man can be fluent in speech even if he is silent, brave even if
his hands are folded, or even tied, just as a man can be a pilot
even when he is on dry land, since there is no deficiency in the
completeness of his knowledge even though something prevents him
from using it, so also a man is grateful who only wishes to be so,
and has <Ess3-247>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxi. 5-xxii. 1
none besides himself to bear witness to this
desire. And I will go even further than this - sometimes a man
is grateful even when he appears to be ungrateful, when rumour with
its evil tongue has given the opposite report of him. What
guide has this man but his own conscience? Crushed though it
be, this gives him cheer, this cries out against the mob and
hearsay, and relies wholly upon itself, and, when it sees the vast
crowd of those on the other side who think differently, it does not
take trouble to count votes, but wins the victory by its single
vote. If it sees its own loyalty subjected to the
chastisements reserved for treachery, it does not descend from its
pinnacle, but abides there superior to its punishment. "I have," it
says, "what I wished, what I strove for; I do not regret it, nor
shall I ever regret it, and no injustice of Fortune shall ever bring
me to such a pass that she will hear me say: 'What was it I
wished? What profit have I now from my good intention?'" I
have profit even on the rack, I have profit even in the fire; though
fire should devour my limbs one by one, and gradually encircle my
living body, though my very heart, brimming with conscious virtue,
should drip with blood, it will delight in the flame through which
its loyalty will shine forth. The following argument
also, although it has already been used, may be reapplied here: why
is it that we wish to be grateful at the hour of death, that we
carefully weigh the services of each one, that, with memory as judge
of the whole of our life, we try to avoid the appearance of having
forgotten the service of any? Nothing then is left for us to
hope for; nevertheless, as we pause upon the threshwold, e <Ess3-249>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxii. l-xxiii. l
wish to appear as grateful as possible at
the time of our departure from human affairs. It is evident
that the great reward for an action lies in the deed itself, and
that virtue has great power in influencing the minds of men, for
souls are flooded with its beauty, and, marvelling at the brilliance
and splendour of it, are transported with enchantment. "But
there are many advantages," you say, "that spring from it; good men
live in greater security, and have the love and respect of good men,
and existence is less troubled when accompanied by innocence and
gratitude." Nature would, indeed, have been most unjust if she had
made so great a good an unhappy and uncertain and unfruitful
thing. But the point to consider is whether you would turn
your steps toward this virtue, which often is reached by a safe and
easy way, even though the path lay over rocks and precipices, and
was beset with wild beasts and serpents. It is not true,
therefore, that that which has also some extraneous profit closely
attached to it is not something to be desired in itself; for in most
cases the things that are most beautiful are accompanied by many
accessory advantages, but they follow in the train of beauty while
she leads the way. Does anyone doubt that the sun and the moon
in their periodic revolutions exercise an influence upon this
abiding-place of the human race? That the heat of the one
gives life to our bodies, loosens the hard earth, reduces excessive
moisture, and breaks off the bonds of gloomy winter that enchains
all things, while the warmth of the other with its efficacious and
pervasive power dtermines the ripening of the crops? That
there is some relation between human fecundity and the course of the
moon? That the one by its <Ess3-251>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxiii. 1-xxiv. 1
circuit marks out the year, and the other,
moving in a smaller orbit, the month? Yet, although these
advantages should be removed, would not the sun itself form a
fitting spectacle for our eyes, and be worthy of our adoration if it
merely passed across the sky? Would not the moon be a sight
worthy of our eyes even if it traversed heaven as idly as a star?
And the firmament itself - who is not held spellbound by it whenever
it pours forth its fires by night and glitters with its horde of
countless stars? Who, when he marvels at them, stops to think
of their utility to himself? Behold the mighty company as it
glides by overhead, how, under the appearance of an organism that is
immovable and at rest, its members conceal from us their
speed. How much takes place in that night of which we take
note only for the purpose of numbering and distinguishing the days!
What a multitude of events is being unrolled beneath this
silence! What a chain of destiny is being traced by their
unerring path! These bodies, which you imagine have been
strewn about for no other purpose than for ornament, are one and all
at work. For there is no reason why you should suppose that
there are only seven wandering stars, and that all the others are
fixed; there are a few whose movements we apprehend, but, farther
removed from our sight, are countless divinities a that go their
rounds, and very many of those that our eyes can reach proceed at an
imperceptible pace and veil their movements. Tell me, would
you not be captivated by the sight of such a mighty structure even
if it did not cover you, guard you, cherish you and give vou birth,
and permeate you with its spirit? As the heavenly bodies have
primarily their use, and are necessary <Ess3-253>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxiv. I-xxv. 2
and vital to us, while it is their majesty
that wholly occupies our minds, so virtue in general, and
particularly that of gratitude, while it does indeed bestow much
upon us, does not wish to be cherished because of this; it has in it
something more, and he who counts it merely among the useful things
has not properly comprehended it. Is a man grateful because it
is to his advantage? Accordingly, also,to the extent that it
is to his advantage? But Virtue does not open her door to a
niggardly lover; he must come to her with an open purse. It is
the ungrateful man who thinks: "I should have liked to return
gratitude, but I fear the expense, I fear the danger, I shrink from
giving offence; I would rather consult my own interest." It is not
possible to render men grateful and ungrateful by the same line of
reasoning; as their actions are different, their intentions are
different. The one is ungrateful, although he ought not to be,
because it is to his interest; the other is grateful, although it is
not to his interest, because he ought to be. It is our aim to
live according to Nature, and to follow the example of the
gods. Yet, in all their acts, what inducement have the gods
other than the very principle of action/a? Unless perchance
you suppose that they obtain a reward for their deeds from the smoke
of burnt offerings and the odour of incense! See the gigantic
efforts they make every day, the great largesses they dispense; with
what wealth of crops they fill the land, with what favourable winds
that bear us to all shores they ruffle the seas, with what mighty
rains, suddenly hurled down, they soften the soil, renew the dried
sources of springs, and, flooding them with secret nourishment, give
them new life! <Ess3-255>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxv. 2-xxvi. 3
They do all these things without any reward,
without attaining any advantage for themselves. Our rule also,
if it would not depart from its model, should observe this principle
of never proceeding to virtuous acts for pay. We should be
ashamed to set a price on any benefit whatsoever - the gods are ours
for nothing! {nature_according_to} "If you are imitating
the gods," you say, "then bestow benefits also upon the ungrateful;
for the sun rises also upon the wicked, and the sea lies open also
to pirates." This point raises the question whether a good man would
bestow a benefit upon one who was ungrateful, knowing that he was
ungrateful. Permit me here to put in a brief remark for fear
that we may be trapped by the tricky question. Understand
that, according to the system of the Stoics, there are two classes
of ungrateful persons. One man is ungrateful because he is a
fool+; a fool is also a bad man a because he is a bad man, he
possesses every vice: therefore he is also ungrateful. Thus we
say that all bad men are intemperate, greedy, voluptuous, and
spiteful, not because every individual has all these vices in a
great or marked degree, but because he is capable of having them;
and he does have them even if they are not visible. Another
man is ungrateful, and this is the common meaning of the term,
because he has a natural tendency to this vice. To an ingrate
of the first type, the man who possesses this fault for the reason
that there is no fault that he does not possess, a good man will
give his benefit; for, if he were to eliminate all such men, there
would be no one to whom he could give. To the ingrate of the
second type, the man who in the matter of benefits shows himself a
cheat, and has a natural bent <Ess3-257>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxvi. 3-xxvli. 3
in this direction, he will no more give a
benefit than he will lend money to a spendthrift, or entrust a
deposit to a man whom many have already found false. There is
the man who is called timid because he is a fool; and because of
this he is classed with the bad men who are beset by all vices
without distinction and without exception. But, strictly
speaking, a timid man is one who because of a natural weakness grows
alarmed even at unmeaning noises. The fool possesses all
vices, but he is not inclined by nature to all; one man inclines to
greed, another to luxury, another to insolence. Therefore it
is a mistake for persons to put such questions as these to the
Stoics: "Tell me, is Achilles timid? Tell me, is
Aristides, whose name stood for justice, unjust? Tell me, is
even Fabius, who retrieved the situation by his delays,"/a
rash? Tell me, is Decius afraid of death? Mucius a
traitor? Camillus a deserter?" We do not say that all men
possess all vices in the same way in which certain men display
particular vices, but that the bad and foolish man is not exempt
from any vice; we do not acquit even the bold man of fear, nor
absolve even the spendthrift from avarice. Just as a man has
all the five senses, and yet all men do not for that reason have as
keen sight as Lynceus/b so, if a man is a fool, he does not possess
all the vices in the same active and vigorous form in which some
persons possess some of them. All the vices exist in all men,
yet not all are equally prominent in each individual. This man's
nature impels him to greed; this one is a victim of wine, this one
of lust, or, if he is not yet a victim, he is so constituted that
his natural impulses lead him in this direction. <Ess3-259>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxvii. 4-xxviii. 2
And so, to return to my
original proposition, everyone who is bad is ungrateful, for he has
in him all the seeds of wrongdoing; yet, strictly speaking, the man
who is termed ungrateful is one who has a bent toward this
vice. To such a man, consequently, I shall not give a
benefit. As a father who betroths his daughter to an
overbearing man who has been often divorced will disregard her best
interests, as he who entrusts the care of his patrimony to one who
has been condemned for the bad management of his affairs will be
considered a poor head of a household, as it will be the veriest
madness for a man to make a will naming as the guardian of his son
one who is known to be a robber of wards, so he will be counted the
worst of benefactors who chooses ungrateful persons in order to
bestow upon them gifts that are doomed to perish. "Even the
gods," you say, "confer many blessings upon the ungrateful." But
they designed them for the good; yet the bad also share in them
because they cannot be separated from the others. It is
better, too, to benefit also the bad for the sake of the good than
to fail the good for the sake of the bad. So the blessings you
cite - the day, the sun, the succession of summer and winter and the
intermediate seasons of spring and autumn with their milder
temperature, rains and springs to drink from, and winds that blow in
fixed season - these the gods have devised for the good of all; they
could not make an exception of individuals. A king gives
honours to the worthy, but largesses even to the unworthy; the thief
no less than the perjurer and the adulterer and everyone, without
distinction of character, whose name appears on the register
receives grain from the state; whatever else <Ess3-261>
ON BENEFITS, IV, xxviii. 2-6
a man may be, he gets his dole, not because
he is good; but because he is a citizen, and the good and the bad
share alike. God also has given certain gifts to the whole
human race, and from these no man is shut out. For, while it was to
the common good that traffic in the sea should be open to all, and
that the kingdom of mankind should be enlarged, it was impossible to
cause the same wind to be favourable for the good and adverse for
the bad; nor was it possible to appoint a law for the fall of the
rains in order that they might not descend upon the fields of wicked
and dishonest men. Certain blessings are offered to all.
Cities are founded as much for the bad as for the good; works of
genius, even if they will fall into the hands of the unworthy, are
published for everybody; medicine points out its healing power even
to criminals; no one has banned the compounding of wholesome
remedies for fear that they may heal the unworthy. In the case
of the gifts that are specifically bestowed because the recipient is
worthy, apply the rule of censorship and of rating the person, but
not so in the case of those that are open to the mob. There is
a great difference between not excluding a man and choosing
him. Justice is vouchsafed even to the thief; even murderers
taste the blessings of peace; those who have stolen the property of
others even recover their own; assassins and those who ply their
swords on the city streets are protected from the public enemy by
the city wall; the laws shield with their protection those who have
sinned most against them. There are certain blessings that
could not have fallen to a few unless they were given to all; there
is no need, therefore, for you to argue about the benefits to which
we have received a public <Ess3-263>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxviii. 6-xxx. 1
invitation. But that which must go to
a beneficiary of my own choosing will not be given to a man whom I
know to be ungrateful. xxx"Will vou, then," you ask, "neither give
counsel to an ungratefull man when he is perplexed, nor permit him
to have a drink of water, nor point out the path to him if he has
lost his way? Or will you do all these services, and yet not
be making a gift?" Here I shall draw a distinction, or at least
endeavour to do so. A benefit is a useful service, but not
every useful service is a benefit; for some services are too small
to have the right to be called benefits. In order to produce a
benefit, there must be a combination of two conditions. The
first is the importance of the service; for there are some that fall
short of the dignity of the claim. Who ever called a morsel of
bread a benefit, or tossing anyone a copper, or enabling, him to get
a light? And sometimes these are more helpful than very large
gifts; yet, for all that, their cheapness detracts from their value
even when the necessity of the moment has made them
necessities. A second condition, which is most important, that
must supplement the other, is that the motive of my action must be
the interest of the one for whom the benefit is destined, that I
should deem him worthy of it, should bestow it willingly and derive
pleasure from my gift; but none of those services of which we were
just speaking bears any of these marks, for we bestow them, not with
the thought that the recipients are worthy, but carelessly and as
mere trifles, and our gift is made, not so much to a man, as to
humanity. I shall not deny that sometimes I shall give even to
the unworthy in order to do honour to others; as, <Ess3-265>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxx. 1-4
for instance, in the competition for public
office some of the most disreputable men are preferred to others who
are industrious, but of no family, by reason of their noble birth,
and not without reason. For sacred is the memory of great
virtues, and more people find pleasure in being good, if the
influence of good men does not end with their lives. To what
did Cicero's son owe the consulship if not to his father? What
recently took Cinna/a from the camp of the enemy, and raised him to
the consulship, what Sextus Pompeius and the other Pompeii, unless
it was the greatness of one man, who once reached such a height that
even his downfall sufficed to exalt all his descendants? What
recently made Fabius Persicus/b a priest in more than one college, a
man whose kiss even the shameless counted an insult? What but
a Verrucosus and an Allobrogicus and the famous three hundred,/c
who, to save their country, blocked the invasion of the enemy with
their single family? This is the duty we owe to the virtuous -
to honour them, not only when they are present with us, but even
when they have been taken from our sight; as they have made it their
aim, not to confine their services to one age alone, but to leave
behind their benefits even after they themselves have passed away,
so let us not confine our gratitude to one age alone.
So-and-so was the father of great men: whatever he may be, he is
worthy of our benefits; he has given us worthy sons. So-and-so
is descended from glorious ancestors: whatever he may be, let him
find refuge under the shadow of his ancestry. As filthy places
become bright from the radiance of the sun, so let the degenerate
shine in the light of their forefathers. <Ess3-267>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxi. 1-5 At this
point, Liberalis, I wish to offer a defence of the gods. For
sometimes we are moved to say: "What could Providence mean by
putting on the throne an Arrhidaeus/a?" Was it to him, think you,
that the honour was accorded? It was accorded to his father
and to his brother. "Why did it make Gaius Caesar the ruler of
the world? - a man so greedy of human blood that he ordered it to be
shed in his presence as freely as if he intended to catch the stream
in his mouth!" But tell me, do you think that it was to him this was
accorded? It was accorded to his father Germanicus, to his
grandfather and to his great- grandfather, and to others before
them, men who were no less glorious, even if they passed their lives
as private citizens on a footing of equality with others. Why,
when you yourself were supporting Mamercus Scaurus/b for the
consulship, were you not aware that he would try to catch in his
open mouth the menstrual discharge of his own maidservants?
Did he himself make any mystery of it? Did he wish to appear
to be decent? I will repeat to you a story that he told on
himself - it went the rounds, I recall, and was recounted in his
presence. To Annius Pollio who was lying down he had proposed,
using an obscene word, an act that he was more ready to submit to,
and when he saw Pollio frown, he added; "If there is anything bad in
what I have said, may it fall upon me and my head!" This story he
used to tell against himself. Is it this man, so openly
obscene, that you have admitted to the fasces and the
tribunal? Of course it was while you were thinking of the
great old Scaurus,/c who was president of the senate, and chafing to
see his offspring obscure! <Ess3-269>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxii. 1-3 The gods,
it is probable, act in the same manner--some are treated with more
indulgence because of their parents and ancestors, others because of
their grandchildren and great- grandchildren and the long line of
their descendants, whose qualities are as yet unrevealed; for the
gods know well the complete evolution of their work, and the
knowledge of all that will hereafter pass through their hands is
always to them clearly revealed. The events that appear
suddenly to us out of the unkdown, and all that we count unexpected
are to them familiar happenings, long foreseen. {Pope+} God says Let these men
be kings {Divine_Right+} because their forefathers
have not been, because they have regarded justice and unselfishness
as their highest authority, because, instead of sacrificing the
state to themselves, they have sacrificed themselves to the state.{Civic_Duty+} Let these others reign,
because some one of their grandsires before them was a good man who
displayed a soul superior to Fortune, who, in times of civil strife,
preferred to be conquered than to conquer, because in this way he
could serve the interest of the state. Despite the long lapse
of time, it has not been possible to pay to him the debt of
gratitude; out of regard for him, now let this other rule over the
people, not because he has the knowledge or the ability, but because
another has served in his place. This one/a is deformed in
body, hideous in aspect, and will bring ridicule upon the insignia
of his office; then men will blame me, they will say that I am blind
and rash, that I little know what disposition I am making of honours
that are due to none but the greatest and loftiest of men; yet I am
well aware that I am making this gift to one man, and thereby paying
an ancient <Ess3-271>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxii. 4-xxxiii. 3
debt to another. How can these critics
know that hero of old, who persistently fled from the glory that
followed him, who, going into danger, had the air that others show
when they return from danger, who never separated his own interest
from that of the state? 'Where,' you ask, 'is this man, or who is
he?' But how could you know these things? It is for me to
balance the debits and credits of such accounts, I know what and to
whom I owe. Some I repay after a long term, others in advance, and
according as opportunity and the resources of my governance permit."
Consequently, I, too, shall sometimes bestow certain gifts on an
ungrateful man, but not because of the man himself. "Tell me," you say,
"if you do not know whether a man is grateful or ungrateful, will
you wait until you do know, or will you refuse to lose the
opportunity of giving a benefit? To wait is a long matter, -
for, as Plato says, the human heart is hard to divine, - not to wait
hazardous." Our answer to this will be that we never wait for
absolute certainty, since the discovery of truth is difficult, but
follow the path that probable truth shows. All the business of
life proceeds in this way. It is thus that we sow, that we sail the
sea, that we serve in the army, that we take wives, that we rear
children ; since in all these actions the issue is uncertain, we
follow the course that we believe offers the hope of success.
For who will promise to the sower a harvest, to the sailor a port,
to the soldier a victory, to a husband a chaste wife, to a father
dutiful children? We follow, not where truth, but where
reason, directs us. If you wait to do only what is assured of
success and to have only the knowledge that comes from ascertained
truth, all activity is given up, and life comes to a halt.
Since <Ess3-273>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxxii. 3-xxxiv. 4
it is, not truth, but the probable truth,
that impels me in one direction or another, I shall give my benefit
to the man who in all probability will be grateful. "Many circumstances,"
you say, "will arise that will enable a bad man to steal into the
place of a good one, and the good man will lose favour instead of
the bad one; for appearances are deceptive, and it is these we
trust." Who denies it? Yet I find nothing else from which to
form an opinion. These are the footprints I must follow in my
search for truth, I have nothing that is more trustworthy; I shall
take pains to consider these with all possible care, and shall not
be hasty in granting my assent. For the same thing may happen
in battle, and my hand, deceived by some mistake, may direct my
weapon against a comrade, and spare an enemy as though he were a
friend; but this will happen but rarely, and from no fault of my
own, for my intention is to smite the enemy, and to defend my
countryman. If I know that a man is ungrateful, I shall not
give him a benefit. Yet if he has tricked me, if he has
imposed upon me, no blame attaches to the giver because I made the
gift supposing that the man would be grateful. "Suppose," you say,
"that you have promised to give a benefit, and later have discovered
that the man is ungrateful, will you or will you not bestow
it? If you do so knowinlylv you do wrong, for you give to one
to whom vou ought not to give; if you refuse, you likewise do wrong
- you do not give to one to whom you promised to give. This
case would upset your conscience and your proud assurance that the
wise man never regrets his action, or amends what he has done, or
changes his purpose." The wise man does not change his purpose if
the situation remains as it <Ess3-275>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxiv. 4-xxxv. 2
was when he formed it; he is never filled
with regret because at the time nothing better could have been done
than was done, no better decision could have been made than was
made; yet all that he undertakes is subject to the
reservation: "If nothing happens to prevent." If we say that
all his plans prosper, and that nothing happens contrary to his
expectation, it is because he has presupposed that something might
happen to thwart his designs. It is the imprudent man who is
confident that Fortune is plighted to himself; the wise man
envisages her in both of her aspects; he knows how great is the
chance of mistake, how uncertain are human affairs, how many
obstacles block the success of our plans; he follows alert the
doubtful and slippery course of chance, weighs uncertain outcome
against his certainty of purpose. But the reservation without
which he makes no plan, undertakes nothing, protects him here
also. I have promised a benefit in case nothing occurs to show
that I ought not to give it. For what if my country should bid
me give to her what I have promised to another? What if a law
should be passed, forbidding anyone to do what I had promised that I
would do for my friend? Suppose I have promised you my
daughter in marriage, but find out later that you are not a citizen;
I have no right to contract a marriage with a foreigner; the same
circumstance that forbids it provides my defence. Only then
shall I be breaking faith, only then shall I listen to a charge of
inconstancy, if I fail to fulfil a promise though all the
circumstances remain the same as they were when I made my promise;
otherwise, any chance that takes place gives me the liberty of
revising my decision, and frees me from my <Ess3-277>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxv. 2-xxxvi. 2
pledge. Suppose I have promised my
legal assistance, but afterwards discover that a precedent was being
sought from that case to harm my father; suppose I have promised
that I will go abroad, but word is brought that the way is beset
with robbers; suppose I was about to go to keep an appointment, but
am detained by the illness of my son or by my wife's
confinement. If you are to hold me to the fulfilment of my
promise+ all the circumstances must remain the same as they
were when I promised; but what greater change can there be than my
discovery that you are a bad and ungrateful man? I shall
refuse to an unworthy man what I was willing to give to him
supposing him to be worthy, and I shall even have reason to be angry
because I was deceived. Nevertheless I shall
also examine into the value of the gift in question; for the amount
of the sum promised will help my decision. If it is a trifle,
I shall give it to you, not because you deserve it, but because I
have promised, and I shall not count it as a gift, but shall keep my
word, and give my ear a twitch. I shall punish my rashness in
promising by suffering loss: "You see how sorry you are for
yourself; next time take more care before you speak!" As the saying
is, I shall pay for my tongue. If the amount is a larger one,
"I shall not," as Maecenas puts it, "let my punishment cost me ten
million sesterces." For I shall match the two sides of the question
one against the other. There is something in abiding by what you
have promised; on the other hand, there is much in the principle of
not bestowing a benefit on one who is unworthy. Yet how great
is this benefit? If it is a slight one, let us wink at it; if,
however, it is likely to cause me either great loss or shame, <Ess3-279>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxvi. 2-xxxvii. 2
should rather excuse myself once for having
refused it than ever afterward for having given it. It all
depends, I say, upon how much value I attach to the letter of my
promise. I shall not only keep back what I have rashly
promised, but shall demand back what I have wrongly given. The
man is mad who keeps a promise that was a mistake. Philip, king of the
Macedonians, had a soldier who was a valiant fighter, and, having
found his services useful in many campaigns, he had from time to
time presented him with some of the booty as a reward for his
prowess, and, by his repeated bounties, was exciting the venal
spirit of the man. Once after being shipwrecked he was cast
ashore upon the estate of a certain Macedonian; this one, when he
heard the news, rushed to his help, resuscitated his breath, brought
him to his farmhouse, surrendered to him his bed, restored him from
a weak and half- dead condition to new life, cared for him for
thirty days at his own expense, put him upon his feet, provided him
with money for his journey, and heard him say over and over:
"I will; how you my gratitude if only I have the good fortune to see
my commander." To Philip he gave an account of his shipwreck, but
said nothing of the help he had received, and promptly asked Philip
to present him with a certain man's estate. The man was, in
fact, his host, the very one who had rescued him, who had restored
him to health. Kings sometimes, especially in time of war,
make many gifts with their eyes closed. "One just man is no match
for so many armed men fired with greed, it is not possible for any
mortal to be a good man and a good general at the same time.
How will he satiate so many thousands of insatiable men? What
will <Ess3-281>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxvil. 3-xxxviii. 1
they have if every man has only what is his
own? So Philip communed with himself as he gave order that the
soldier should be put in possession of the property he asked
for. The other, however, when he was expelled from his
property, did not, like a peasant, endure his wrong in silence,
thankful that he himself had not been included in the present, but
wrote a concise and outspoken letter to Philip. Upon receiving
this, Philip was so enraged that he immediately ordered Pausanias/a
to restore the property to its former owner, and, besides, to brand
that most dishonourable of soldiers, most ungrateful of guests, most
greedy of shipwrecked men with letters showing him to be an
ungrateful person. He, indeed, deserved, not merely to be
branded with those letters, but to have them carved in his flesh - a
man who had cast out his own host to lie like a naked and
shipwrecked sailor upon that shore on which he himself had
lain. But we shall heed within what limits the punishment
ought to be kept; he had, in any case, to be deprived of what he had
seized with the utmost villainy. Yet who would be moved by his
punishment? He had committed a crime which could stir no
pitiful heart to pity him. Will a Philip give to
you because he promised, even at the price of sacrificing duty, even
at the price of committing an injustice, even at the price of
committing a crime, even at the price of closing all shores/b to the
shipwrecked by this one act? There is no fickleness in leaving
a wrong course when it has been recognized as such and condemned,
and we must confess frankly: "I thought it was different, I
have been deceived." It is but the stubbornness of foolish pride to
declare: "What I have once said, be it what <Ess3-283>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xxxviii. 2-xxxix. 3
it may, shall remain fixed and unaltered."
There is nothing wrong in changing a plan when the situation is
changed. Tell me, if Philip had left the soldier in possession
of the shores that he had obtained by shipwreck, is it not true that
he would thereby have cut off all unfortunates from fire and
water/a? "Rather do you," he said, "within the bounds of my
kingdom carry everywhere upon your most brazen brow these letters
that ought to be stamped upon all men's eyes. Go, show how
sacred a thing is the table of hospitality; display upon your
countenance that decree, for all to read, which keeps it from being
a capital crime to shelter the unfortunate beneath one's roof!
This ordinance will thus have more authority than if I had engraved
it upon bronze." "Why, then," you say, "did your master Zeno, when
he had promised a loan of five hundred denarii to a man, and had
himself discovered that he was an altogether unsuitable person,
persist in making the loan because he had promised it, although his
friends advised him not to give it?" In the first place, one set of
terms applies to a loan, another to a benefit. It is possible
to recall money even if it has been badly placed; I can summon a
debtor to pay on a given date, and, if he has gone bankrupt, I shall
get my share; but a benefit is lost wholly and immediately. Besides,
the one is the act of a bad man, the other of a bad manager.
Again, if the sum had been a larger one, not even Zeno would have
persisted in lending it. It was only five hundred denarii, -
an amount, as we say, "one can spend on an illness," - and not to
break his promise+ was worth that much. I will
go out to dinner because I have promised, even if the weather is
cold; but not so if there is a snowstorm. <Ess3-285>
ON BENEFITS, IV.
ix.3-XL. 2
I will rise from my table because I have
promised to attend a betrothal, although I have not digested my
food; but not so if I shall have a fever. I will go down to the
forum in order to go bail for you because I have promised; but not
so if you ask me to go bail for an uncertain amount, if you place me
under obligation to the treasury./a There is understood, I say, the
unexpressed reservations: "If I can, if I ought,if things
remain so-and- so." When you exact fulfilment, see to it that
the situation is the same as it was when I promised; then, if I
fail, I shall be guilty of fickleness. If something new has
happened, why are you surprised that my intention has changed, since
conditions have changed since I promised? Put everything back as it
was, and I shall be as I was. We promise to appear in court,
yet not all are liable to prosecution if they default - a major
necessity excuses the defaulter. {promises+} To the further
question of whether in every case we ought to show gratitude, and
whether a benefit ought in all cases to be returned, consider that I
make the same reply. It is my duty to show a grateful heart,
but sometimes my own ill fortune, sometimes the good fortune of the
one to whom I am indebted, will not permit me to show gratitude. For
what return can I make to a king, what to a rich man if I am poor,
particularly since some men regard it as an ijustice to have their
benefit returned, and are continually piling benefits upon
benefits? In the case of such persons, what more can I do than
have the desire? Nor, indeed, ought I to refuse a fresh
benefit simply because I have not yet repaid an earlier one. I
shall accept it as willingly as it is given, and I shall allow my
friend to find in me an ample opportunity for <Ess3-287>
ON BENEFITS, IV. xl. 2-5) |
exercising his goodness. He who is
unwilling to accept new benefits must resent those already
received. I may not testify my gratitude - but what does it
matter? I am not responsible for the delay if I lack either
the opportunity or the means. He of course, had both the
opportunity and the means when he bestowed his benefit upon
me. Is he a good man or a bad man? Before a good judge I
have a good case; before a bad one I do not plead my case. Nor
do I think that we ought to do this either - to hasten to show
gratitude even against the will of those to whom we show it, and to
press it upon them although they draw back. It is not
displaying gratitude to repay something that you have willingly
accepted to someone who is unwilling to accept it. Some
people, when a trifling gift has been sent to them, forthwith, quite
unseasonably, send back another, and then declare that they are
under no obligation; but to send something back at once, and to wipe
out a gift with a gift is almost a repulse. Sometimes, too, I
shall not return a benefit although I am able. When?
When I myself shall lose more than the other will gain, when he will
not be aware of any increase of his store in taking back that which
will cause me great loss by being returned. He who hastens at
all odds to make return shows the feeling, not of a person that is
grateful, but of a debtor. And, to put it briefly, he who is
too eager to pay his debt is unwilling to be indebted, and he who is
unwilling to be indebted is ungrateful.
<Ess3-289>
BOOK V
I thought that I
had finished my task in the preceding books, having discussed there
how a benefit ought to be given, and how it ought to be received;
for these two points are the boundary marks of this particular
service. In any further inquiry, I shall be, not serving, but
indulging, my subject, the only demand of which is that I follow
whither it leads, not whither it allures; for now and then a
suggestion will be born that challenges the mind by a certain charm,
yet remains, if not a useless, an unnecessary addition. Since,
however, such is your wish, having finished with the matters that
bound the subject, let us continue to examine further those that, if
I must tell the truth, are associated with it, yet are not actually
connected; whoever examines these carefully will neither be repaid
for his pains nor yet wholly waste his pains. To you, however,
Aebutius Liberalis, who are naturally the best of men and prone to
benefits, no laudation of them seems to be adequate. Never
have I seen anyone who was so generous in his estimate of even the
most trivial services; your goodness has reached such a degree that,
when any man is given a benefit, you count it as given to yourself;
in order that no one may regret the bestowal of a benefit, you are
ready to pay the debts of the <Ess3-291>
ON BENEFITS, V. 1. 4-ii. 2
ungrateful. So far removed are you
yourself from all boasting, so eager at once to free those whom you
place under obligation from the burden of it, that, in making a gift
to anyone, you wish to appear, not to be bestowing, but to be
returning, one; and so all that is given in this manner will be
returned to you in richer measure. For benefits usually pursue
the man who asks no return, and just as glory is more apt to pursue
those who flee from it, so those who are willing to allow men to be
ungrateful reap a more grateful return for the benefits they have
given them. Truly, so far as you are concerned, there is
nothing to prevent those who have received benefits from boldly
repeating their request, nor will you refuse to confer others, and
to add more and greater benefits to those that have been covert and
concealed - excellent man that you are and a truly great soul, your
aim is to bear with an ungrateful man so long that he will in the
end become grateful. Nor will your method deceive you; vices
will yield to virtue if you do not hasten too quickly to hate
them. In any case the precept that it is disgraceful to be
outdone in bestowing benefits+ gives you unique pleasure as
being a glorious utterance. Whether this is true or not is
often rightly questioned, and the case is quite different from what
you imagine. For it is never disgraceful to be worsted in a
struggle for something honourable, provided that you do not throw
down your arms, and that, even when conquered, you still wish to
conquer. Not all bring the same strength to the accomplishment
of a good purpose, nor the same resources, nor the same favour of
Fortune, which modifies at all events the issues of even the best
plans; praise should be awarded to the very desire <Ess3-293>
ON BENEFITS, V. ii. 2-iii. 1
that strives in the right direction even
though another by his swifter pace outstrips it. It is not as
in the contests provided as a public spectacle, where the palm
declares which is the better contestant, although even in these
chance often gives the preference to the poorer man. When the
object of the struggle is a service which both on their part are
eager to make as great as possible, if one of the two has had
greater power, and has had at hand ample resources to accomplish his
purpose, if Fortune permits him to attain all that he has attempted,
while the other matches him only in desire - even if the latter has
returned smaller gifts than he received, or, has not returned all,
but wishes to make return, and strives with his whole soul to do so,
he is no more conquered than is the soldier who dies in arms, whom
the enemy could more easily kill than turn from his purpose. You are
counting it a disgrace to be conquered, but that cannot possibly
happen to a good man. For he will never surrender, he will
never give up; to the last day of his life he will stand prepared,
and in that posture will die, proud of having received great gifts
and of having desired to repay them. The Lacedaemonians
forbid their young men to contend in the pancratium/a or with the
caestus, where the weaker contestant is shown by his own admission
that he has been conquered. A runner wins by being the first
to reach the chalk-line; he surpasses his opponent, not in pluck but
in speed. A wrestler who has been thrown three times, though
he does not surrender the palm, loses it. Since the
Lacedaemonians thought it highly important to have their citizens
invincible, they kept them out of those contests in which the victor
is determined, not by a judge, or <Ess3-295>
ON BENEFITS, V. iii. 1-iv. 1
purely by the outcome itself, but by the cry
of the vanquished proclaiming surrender., This quality of never
being conquered, which the Lacedaemonians safeguard for their
citizens, is bestowed on all men by virtue and virtuous desire,
since the spirit is unconquered even in the midst of defeat.
For this reason no one speaks of the three hundred Fabii as
conquered, but slaughtered; and Regulus was captured by the
Carthaginians, not conquered, nor is any other man who, though
overwhelmed by the strength and weight of angry Fortune, does not
yield in spirit. The same is true of benefits. A man may have
received more than he gave, greater ones, more frequent ones, yet,
for all that, he has not been conquered. If you reckon those
that you have given over against those that you have received, it is
true, perhaps, that benefits are surpassed by benefits; but, if you
match the giver against the recipient, taking into consideration, as
you must, their intentions in themselves, the palm will belong to
neither. For, even when one combatant has been pierced by many
wounds, while the other has been but slightly wounded, it is
customary to say that they left the arena evenly matched, although
it is evident that one of them is the weaker man. xxx No one,
therefore, can be outdone in benefits if he knows how to owe a debt,
if he desires to make return - if he matches his benefactor in
spirit, even though he cannot match him in deeds. So long as
he continues in this state of mind, so long as he holds the desire
to give proof of a grateful heart, what difference does it make on
which side the greater number of gifts is reckoned? You are
able to give much, and I am able only to receive; on your side
stands good fortune, on my side good desire; yet I am as <Ess3-297>
ON BENEFITS, V. iv. 1-v. 1
much your peer as naked or lightly armed
soldiers are the peers of the many who are fully armed. No
one, therefore, is outdone in benefits because each man's gratitude
is to be measured by his desire. For, if it is disgraceful to
be outdone in benefits it is not right to accept a benefit from most
powerful men whose kindness you are unable to return - I mean
princes and kings, who have been placed by Fortune in a position
that enables them to bestow many gifts, and are likely to receive
very few and very inadequate returns for what they have given.
I have spoken of kings and princes, to whom, nevertheless, it is
possible for us to render assistance, and whose preeminent power
rests upon the consent and service of their inferiors. But there are
some men who, withdrawn beyond.the reach of every lust, are scarcely
touched at all by any human desires; upon whom Fortune herself has
nothing that she can bestow. In benefits I must of necessity
be outdone by Socrates, of necessity by Diogenes,/a who marchea
naked through the midst of the treasures of the Macedonians,
treading under foot the wealth of kings. O! in very truth, how
rightly did he seem then, both to himself and to all others who had
not been rendered blind to the perception of truth, to tower above
the man beneath whose feet lay the whole world! Far more
powerful, far richer was he than Alexander, who then was master of
the whole world; for what Diogenes refused to receive was even more
than Alexander was able to give. {poor_is_rich+}
It is not
disgraceful to be outdone by such as these for it is not proved that
I am the less brave if you pit me against an enemy that is
invulnerable, nor that fire is the less able to burn if it falls
upon a substance <Ess3-299>
ON BENEFITS, V. v. 1-4
that flames cannot harm, nor that iron has
lost its power of cutting if it attempts to cleave stone that is
solid, impervious to a blow, and by its very nature invincible to
hard instruments. In regard to the grateful man I would answer
you in the same way. He is not disgracefully outdone in
benefits if he has become indebted to those whose exalted station or
exceeding merit blocks the approach to any benefits that might
return to them. Our parents almost always outdo us. For,
so long as we count them severe, so long as we fail to understand
the benefits they give us, we have them with us. When at last
with age we have acquired some wisdom, and it begins to be evident
that we ought to love them for the very things that kept us from
loving them - their admonitions, their strictness, and their careful
watch over our heedless youth - they are snatched from us. Few reach
the age when they can reap some true reward from their children; the
rest are aware of their sons by their burden. Yet there is no
disgrace in being outdone in benefits by a parent; how should there
be, seeing that there is no disgrace in being outdone by
anyone? For there are some men to whom we are both equal and
unequal - equal in intention, which is all that they require,
unequal in fortune, and, if it is this that prevents anyone from
repaying a favour, he has no need to blush on the ground that he has
been outdone. It is no disgrace to fail to attain provided you
keep striving. Very often it is necessary to ask for new
benefits before we have returned older ones, and yet we do not fail
to ask for them or feel any disgrace because we shall be indebted
for them with no prospect of returning them, for, if we are
prevented from showing ourselves most grateful, it will be the <Ess3-301>
ON BENEFITS, V. v. 4-vi. 2
fault, not of ourselves, but of something
from without that intervenes and deters us. Yet in intention
we shall not be outdone, nor shall we be disgraced if we are
overpowered by things that are beyond our control. Alexander, king
of the Macedonians, used to boast that no one had outdone him in
benefits. But there is no reason why, in the excess of his
pride, he should look up to the Macedonians and the Greeks and the
Carians and the Persians and the other nations who were enrolled in
his army, nor suppose that it was their benefit that had bestowed
upon him a kingdom that extended from a corner of Thrace to the
shore of the unknown sea! Socrates could have had the same
reason to boast, and Diogenes the same reason, by whom, in any case,
he was outdone. Why was he not outdone on that day when,
puffed up as he was beyond the limits of human pride, he saw someone
to whom he could give nothing, from whom he could take nothing away?
King Archelaus
once invited Socrates to come to him. But Socrates is said to
have replied that he was not willing to go to him in order that he
might receive benefits from him, since he would be unable to make
adequate return for them. Yet, in the first place, he was at
liberty to refuse to accept them; in the second place, he would have
anticipated him in bestowing a benefit, for he would have come
because he was invited, and would, at any rate, have given something
for which Archelaus could have made no return to Socrates.
Furthermore, if Archelaus was going to give to him gold and silver,
and was going to receive in return only a scorn for gold and silver,
could not Socrates have repaid Archelaus with his <Ess3-303>
ON BENEFITS, V. vi. 3-5
thanks? And what could he have
received that would have had the value of what he gave if he had
revealed to Archelaus a man who was skilled in the knowledge of life
and of death, and comprehended the ends of both? If he had admitted
into the secrets of Nature one who even in broad daylight had lost
his way - a king, so ignorant of her ways that one day, when there
was an eclipse of the sun, he shut up his palace, and, as is
customary in times of grief and disaster, sheared his son's
hair/a? How great a benefit it would have been if Socrates had
dragged the frightened king from his hiding-place, and bidden him be
of good cheer, saying: "This does not mean the disappearance
of the sun, but that two heavenly bodies are in conjunction by
reason of the fact that the moon, which travels by a lower path has
placed her disk exactly beneath the sun itself, and has hidden it by
interposing her own body. Sometimes, if she just grazes the
sun in passing, she veils only a small portion of it; sometimes, if
she thrusts the greater part of her body in front of it, she
conceals a larger portion; sometimes, if, being between the earth
and the sun, she reaches a point where the three bodies are in a
straight line, she shuts off completely the sight of the sun.
But soon their own speed will draw these heavenly bodies apart, one
to this position, the other to that; soon the earth will recover the
light of day. And this order Will continue throughout the
ages. and has its appointed days, that are known beforehand, on
which the sun is prevented from sending forth all his rays because
of the intervention of the moon. Wait just a little while;
soon he will emerge, soon he will leave behind this seeming cloud,
soon he <Ess3-305>
ON BENEFITS, V. vi. 6-vii. 2
will be rid of all obstructions, and will
freely send forth his light." Could not Socrates have made adequate
return to Archelaus for his favour if he had forbidden him to be
king/a? Assuredly the benefit he received from Socrates would
have been too small if it had been possible for him to bestow any
benefit on Socrates! Why, then, did Socrates says this?
Being a clever person, who was given to talking in parables, a
mocker of all, especially of the great, he preferred to couch his
refusal in irony rather than in stubbornness or pride; he said that
he was not willing to receive benefits from one to whom he could not
make adequate return. Perhaps he feared that he might be
forced to accept gifts that he did not wish, that he might be forced
to accept something unworthy of Socrates. Someone will
say: "He could have refused it if he wished." But he would
have made an enemy of the king, who was arrogant, and wished all his
favours to be highly valued. Whether you are unwilling to give
something to a king, or to accept something from a king is of no
consequence; both alike are in his eyes a rebuff, and to be treated
with scorn is more bitter to a proud spirit than not to be
feared. Would you like to know what Socrates really meant? He
meant that the man whose freedom of speech even a free state could
not endure declined to enter into voluntary servitude! But I think that we
have sufficiently discussed this topic of whether it is disgraceful
to be outdone in benefits. Whoever raises the question must
know that men are not in the habit of bestowing benefits upon
themselves; for it would have been evident that there is no disgrace
in a man's being outdone by himself. Yet among certain Stoics
it is even debated <Ess3-307>
ON BENEFITS, V. vii. 2-5
whether it is possible for a man to bestow a
benefit on himself, whether it is his duty to return gratitude to
himself. The reason why it seemed necessary to raise the
question was our habitual use of such expressions as: "I am
thankful to myself," "I can blame no one but myself," "I am angry
with myself," "I shall exact punishment from myself," "I hate
myself" and, many others of the same sort in which one speaks of
oneself as if another person. "If," they say, "I am able to
injure myself, why should I not be able, also to bestow a benefit on
myself? Moreover, why should not things that would be called
benefits if I had bestowed them on another still be benefits if I
have bestowed them on myself? Why should not something that
would have placed me in debt if I had received it from another still
place me in debt if I have given it to myself? Why should I be
ungrateful to myself, which is just as disgraceful as to be
niggardly to oneself and harsh and cruel to oneself and neglectful
of oneself? The reputation of a pimp is equally bad whether he
prostitutes himself or another. The flatterer, the man who
subscribes to the words of another, and is ready to applaud
falsehoods, is of course open to censure; and not less so is the man
who is pleased with himself, who, so to speak, looks up to himself,
and is his own flatterer. The vices are hateful, not only when
they are outwardly expressed, but when they are turned in upon
themselves. Whom will you more admire than the man who governs
himself, who has himself under control? It is easier to rule savage
nations, impatient as they are of the authority of others, than to
restrain one's own spirit and submit to selfcontrol. Plato, say
they, was grateful to Socrates be- <Ess3-309>
ON BENEFITS, V. vii. 5-viii. 2
cause he learned from him; why should not
Socrates be grateful to himself because he taught himself?
Marcus Cato says: 'Borrow from yourself whatever you lack.' If I am
able to lend to myself, why should I not be able to give to
myself? The instances in which habit leads us to divide
ourselves into two persons are countless; we are prone to say: 'Let
me converse with myself,' and, 'I will give my ear a twitch.'/a If
there is any truth in these expressions, just as a man ought to be
angry with himself, so he ought to render thanks to himself; as he
ought to reprove himself, so also he ought to praise himself; as he
can cause himself loss, so also he can bring himself gain.
Injury and benefit are the converse of each other; if we say of
anyone: 'He has done himself an injury,' we may also say: 'He has
bestowed upon himself a benefit.'" Nature's rule is that a man
should first become a debtor, and then should return gratitude;
there cannot be a debtor without a creditor any more than there can
be a husband without a wife, - or a father without a son; someone
must give in order that someone may receive. To transfer
something from the left hand to the right hand is neither to give
nor to receive. Just as no one carries himself although he
moves and transports his body, as no one, although he has spoken in
his own defence, is said to have appeared as his own advocate, or
erects a statue to himself as his own patron, as no sick man, when
he has regained health by treating himself, demands from himself a
fee, so in transactions of every sort - even though he may have done
something that has been to his advantage, yet he will be under no
obligation to return gratitude to himself because he will not find
<Ess3-311>
ON BENEFITS, V. viii. 3-6
any person to whom he can return it.
Though I grant that a man may bestow a benefit on himself, yet at
the same time that he gives it, he also receives a return; though I
grant that a man may receive a benefit from himself, yet at the same
time that he receives it, he returns it. "You borrow," as they
say, "from your own pocket," and, just as if it were a game, the
item immediately shifts to the other side/a; for the giver and the
receiver are not to be differentiated, but are one and the same
person. The word "owe" has no place unless two persons are
involved; how, then, will it apply to one person, who, in the act of
incurring a debt, frees himself from it? In a disk or a sphere
there is no bottom, no top, no end, no beginning, because as the
object is moved, the relations change, and the part that was behind
now precedes, and the part that was going down now comes up, yet
all, in whatever direction they may move, come back to the same
position. Imagine that the same principle applies in the case of a
man; though you may transform him into many different characters, he
remains a simple human being. He strikes himself - there is no
one whom he may charge with doing him an injury. He binds
himself and locks himself up - he is not held for damages. He
bestows a benefit on himself - he has forthwith made return to the
giver. In the
realm of Nature, it is said, there is never any loss, for whatever
is taken out of it, returns to it, and nothing is able to perish,
because there is no place into which it can escape, but everything
returns to whence it came. "What is the bearing," you ask, "of
this illustration on the question that is before us?" I will tell
you. Suppose that you are un- <Ess3-313>
ON BENEFITS, V. viii. 6-ix. 3
grateful - the benefit is not lost, for the
one who bestowed it still has it, Suppose that you are unwilling to
receive a return - it is already in your possession before it is
returned. You are not able to lose anything, because what is
withdrawn from you is none the less acquired by you. The
operation proceeds in a circle within yourself - in receiving you
give, in giving you receive. "One ought," you say,
"to bestow benefit on oneself; therefore one ought also to return
gratitude to oneself." But the first proposition, on which the
conclusion depends, is false; for no one bestows benefit on himself,
but a man simply obeys a natural instinct that disposes him to show
affection for himself, and it is this that causes him to take the
utmost pains to avoid what is hurtful, and to seek what is
beneficial. Consequently, the man who gives to himself is not
generous, nor is he who pardons himself merciful, nor he who is
touched by his own misfortunes pitiful. For generosity, mercy,
and pity contribute to others; natural instinct contributes to
oneself. A benefit is a voluntary act, but self-interest is a
law of nature. The more benefits a man bestows, the more
beneficent he becomes; but who was ever praised for having been of
service to himself? for having rescued himself from brigands?
No one any more bestows a benefit upon himself than he does
hospitality; no one any more gives to himself than he lends to
himself. If every
man does bestow benefits on himself, if he is always bestowing them,
and bestows them without cessation, it will be impossible for him to
reckon the number of his benefits. When, then, will he be able
to return gratitude, since, by the act of returning gratitude, he
will be giving a benefit? For how will <Ess3-315>
ON BENEFITS, V, ix. 3-x. 2
you be able to tell whether he is giving, or
returning, a benefit to himself, since the transactions take place
within one and the same man? I have freed myself from peril - I
have, then, bestowed a benefit upon myself. I free myself from
peril a second time - am I, then, giving, or returning, a benefit to
myself? Again,
although I should grant the first proposition, that we do bestow
benefit upon ourselves, I shall not grant the conclusion that is
drawn from it; for even if we give, we owe nothing. Why?
because we immediately receive a return. I ought, properly, to
receive a benefit, then be indebted, then repay; but there is no
opportunity here to be indebted, for we receive a return without any
delay. No one really gives except to another, no one owes
except to another, no one return's except to another. An act that so
often requires two persons cannot be performed within the limits of
one. A benefit is
the contribution of something useful but "contribution" implies the
existence of others. If a man says that he has sold something
to himself, will he not be thought mad? For selling means
alienation, the transferring of one's property and one's right in it
to another. Yet, just as is the case in selling, giving
implies the relinquishment of something, the surrendering of
something that you have held to the possession of another. And
if this is so, no one has ever bestowed a benefit upon himself
because no one can "give" to himself; otherwise two opposites are
combined in one act, so that giving and receiving are the same
thing. Yet there is a great difference between giving and
receiving; why should there not be, since these words are applied to
exactly <Ess3-317>
ON BENEFITS, V, x. 2-xi. 1
opposite actions? Yet, if anyone can
give a benefit to himself, there is no difference between giving and
receiving. I said a little while ago that certain words imply
the existence of other persons, and are of such fashion that their
whole meaning is directed away from ourselves. I am a brother,
but of another, for no one can be his own brother; I am an equal,
but of someone else, for can any man be the equal of himself?
Unless there are two objects, comparison is unintelligible; unless
there are two objects, there can be no coupling; so also, unless
there are two persons, there can be no giving, and, unless there are
two persons, there can be no benefaction. This is clear from the
very expression, "to do good to," by which the act is defined; but
no one any more does good to himself than he befriends himself, or
belongs to his own party. I might pursue this theme further,
and multiply examples. Of course, since benefaction must be
included among those acts that require a second person.
Certain actions, though honourable, admirable, and highly virtuous,
find a field only in the person of another. Fidelity is praised, and
honoured as one of the greatest blessings of the human race, yet is
it ever said that anyone for that reason has kept his promise to
himself? I come
now to the last part of the subject. He who returns gratitude ought
to expend something, just as he who pays a debt expends money; but
he who returns gratitude to himself expends nothing, just as surely
as he who has received a benefit from himself gains nothing. A
benefit and the repayment of gratitude must pass from one to the
other; no interchange is possible if only one person is
involved. He who returns gratitude does good in his turn to
the one <Ess3-319>
ON BENEFITS, V. xi. 1-6
from whom he obtained something. But
he who returns gratitude to himself - to whom does he do good?
Only to himself. And who does not think of the repayment of
gratitude as one act, and the bestowal of a benefit as another? He
who returns gratitude to himself does good to himself. And
what ingrate was ever unwilling to do this? Nay, rather, who
was ever an ingrate except that he might do this? "If," you
say, "we ought to render thanks to ourselves, we ought also to
return gratitude; yet we say: 'I am thankful to myself that I
refused to marry that woman,' and 'that I did not conclude a
partnership with that man.' "But when we say this, we are lauding
ourselves, and, in order to show approval of our act, we misapply
the language of those who render thanks. A benefit is
something which, when given, May, or may not, be returned. Now
he who gives a benefit to himself cannot help having what he has
given returned; therefore this is not a benefit. A benefit is
received at one time, is returned at another./a A benefit, too,
possesses this commendable, this most praiseworthy, quality, that a
man forgets for the time being his own interest in order that he may
give help to another, that he is ready to deprive himself of what he
gives to another. But he who gives a benefit to himself does
not do this. The giving of a benefit is a social act, it wins
the goodwill of someone, it lays someone under obligation; giving to
oneself is not a social act, it wins no one's goodwill, it lays no
one under obligation, it raises no man's hopes, or leads him to say:
"I must cultivate this man; he has given a benefit to So-and-so, he
will give one to me also." A benefit is something that a man gives,
not for his own sake, but for the sake <Ess3-321>
ON BENEFITS, V. xi. 6-xii. 3
of the one to whom he is giving. But
he who gives a benefit to himself gives for his own sake; this,
then, is not a benefit. I seem to you now to
have been false to the claim that I made at the beginning. For
you say that I am far from doing anything worth while - nay, that,
in honest truth, I am wasting all my trouble. But wait, and
you will soon say this with more truth after I have led you into
such obscurities that, even when you have found your way out, you
will have accomplished nothing more than escape from difficulties
into which you need never have plunged. For what is the good
of laboriously untying knots which you yourself have made in order
that you might untie them? But, just as it provides amusement
and sport when certain objects are knotted up in such a way that an
unskilled person has difficulty in unloosing them, while they yield
without any trouble to the one who tied the knots because he knows
the loops and the snarls, and nevertheless the problem affords some
pleasure, for it tests sharpness of wits and provokes mental effort,
so these matters, which seem cunning and tricky, banish indifference
and sloth from our minds, which, at one time, should find a level
field in which to wander, and, at another, should encounter a dark
and uneven stretch, through which we must merely creep, and place
every footstep with care. Some argue that no man is
ungrateful, and support the statement as follows: "a benefit
is that which does good; but, according to you Stoics, no one is
able to do good to a bad man; therefore a bad man does not receive a
benefit, <therefore he> is <not> ungrateful. <Ess3-323>
ON BENEFITS, V. xii. 3-7
xxx"Furthermore, you say, a benefit is an
honourable and commendable act; but no honourable and commendable
act has place in a bad man, therefore neither has a benefit; and, if
he cannot receive one, neither ought he to return one, and,
therefore, he does not become ungrateful. "Furthermore,
according to you, a good man always acts rightly; but, if he always
acts rightly, he cannot be ungrateful. No one is able to give a
benefit to a bad man. A good man returns a benefit, a bad man
does not receive one; and, if this is so, neither is any good man,
nor any bad man, ungrateful. So in the whole realm of Nature,
there is no such thing as an ungrateful man, and the term is an
empty one."
According to us Stoics there is only one sort of good, the
honourable. {honestum+} A bad man cannot possibly
attain this; for he will cease to be bad if virtue has entered into
him; but, so long as he is bad, no one is able to give him a
benefit, because evils and goods are opposites, and cannot
unite. Therefore, no one can do good to him, for whatever good
reaches him is vitiated by his wrong use of it. Just as the
stomach, when it is impaired by discase, gathers bile, and, changing
all the food that it receives, turns every sort of sustenance into a
source of pain, so, in the case of the perverse mind, whatever you
entrust to it becomes to it a burden and a source of disaster and
wretchedness. And so those who are most prosperous and wealthy
are beset with most trouble, and the more property they have to
cause them unrest, the less they find themselves. Nothing,
therefore, which would be to their good can possibly come to bad men
- nay, nothing which would not do them harm. For whatever good
falls to their lot they change into their <Ess3-325>
ON BENEFITS, V. xii. 7-xiii. 3
own evil nature, and seemingly attractive
gifts that would be beneficial if they were given to a better man
become baneful to them. Nor, therefore, are they able to give
a benefit, since no one is able to give what he does not have; such
a man lacks the desire to benefit, But, though this is
so, still even a bad man is able to receive certain things that
resemble benefits, and he will be ungrateful if he does not return
them. There are goods of the mind, goods of the body, and
goods of fortune. The fool and the bad man are debarred from
the goods of the mind; but he is admitted to the others - these he
can receive and ought to return, and, if he does not return them, he
is ungrateful. And ours is not the only school that holds this
doctrine. The Peripatetics also, who widely extend the bounds
of human happiness, say that trifling benefits come even to the bad,
and that he who does not return such is ungrateful. We,
therefore, do not agree that things that will not make the mind
better are benefits; nevertheless we do not deny that those things
are advantageous and desirable. These things a bad man is able
both to give to a good man and to receive from him, such as money
and clothing and public office and life; and, if he does not return
them, he will fall into the class of the ungrateful. xxx "But," you
retort, "how can you call a man ungrateful if he fails to return
something which you will not admit to be a benefit?" Certain things,
on account of their similarity, are designated by the same term even
at the expense of some inaccuracy. Thus we speak of a silver
and a golden "pyxis/a"; thus, too, we call a man "illiterate,"
though he may <Ess3-327>
ON BENEFITS, V. xiii. 3-xiv. 3
be not utterly untutored but only not
acquainted with the higher branches of learning; thus, too, one who
has seen a man wretchedly clad and in rags says that the man he saw
was "naked." The things that we mean are not really benefits, but
have the appearance of benefits. "Then," you retort, "just as
these things are quasi-benefits, so also the man is, not an ingrate,
but a quasi-ingrate." No, not so, because both the giver and the
recipient of these things call them benefits. So, he who fails
to return the semblance of a true benefit is just as much an ingrate
as he is a poisoner who, when he thought that he was concocting
poison, concocted a sleeping-draught! The words of
Cleanthes/a are even stronger. "Granted," he says, "that what the
man received was not a benefit, yet he himself is an ingrate
because, even if he had received a benefit, he would not have
returned it." So, a man becomes a brigand even before he stains his
hands with blood, because he has armed himself to kill, and
possesses the desire to murder and rob; he practises and manifests
wickedness in action, but it does not begin there. Men are
punished for sacrilege, but no man's hands can actually reach the
gods. "How," it is asked, "can anyone be ungrateful to a bad
man, since a bad man is unable to give a benefit?" For the reason,
of course, that, while the gift that was received was not a benefit,
it was called one. If anyone receives from a bad man any of
these things that the ignorant/b possess, of which even the bad have
a store, it will be his duty to be grateful with a like offering,
and, no matter what may be the nature of the gifts, to return them
as true goods since he received them as true goods. A man is
<Ess3-329>
ON BENEFITS, V. xiv. 4-xv. 3
said to be in debt/a whether he owes pieces
of gold or pieces of leather stamped with the seal of the state,
such as the Lacedaemonians used, which serve the purpose of coined
money. Discharge your indebtedness in that kind by which you
incurred it. What benefits are, whether so great and noble a
term should be degraded by being applied to such mean and vulgar
matter, does not concern you; your search for truth is to the
detriment of others. Do you adjust your minds to the semblance
of truth, and, while you are learning true virtue, honour whatever
vaunts the name of virtue. "As, according to
you," I someone retorts, "no man is ungrateful, so, on the other
hand, all men are ungrateful." Yes, for, as we say, all fools are
bad; moreover, he who has one vice has them all; but all men are
foolish and bad; all men, therefore, are ungrateful. What,
then? Are they not? Is it not an indictment that is
everywhere brought against the human race? Is it not a
universal complaint that benefits are thrown away, that there are
only a very few who do not requite those who have treated them
kindly with the greatest unkindness? Nor need you suppose that
I am merely voicing the grumbling of the Stoics, who count every act
as most evil and wrong that falls short of the standard of
righteousness. Hear the voice of one who cries out condemnation upon
all nations and peoples, a voice that issues, not from the home of
philosophy, but from the midst of the crowd!
No guest from host is safe,
nor daughter's sire From daughter's
spouse; e'en brothers' love is rare. The
husband doth his wife, she him, ensnare./b -------- b Ovid, Met. i. 144 sqq., cited also in De Ira,
ii. 9. 2. <Ess3-331>
ON BENEFITS, V. xv. 4-xvi. 1
This goes even further - here crime takes
the place of benefits, and the blood of those for whom blood ought
to be shed is not spared; we requite benefits with the sword and
poison. To lay hands upon the fatherland itself and crush it
with its own fasces is to gain rank and power. Whoever does
not stand above the commonweal thinks that he stands in a position
that is low and degraded. The armies that she has given are
turned against herself, and the general now harangues his men
with: "Fight against your wives, fight against your
children! Assail with arms your altars, hearths, and household
gods!" Yes, you who had no right to enter the city without the
permission of the senate even in order to triumph, who, when
bringing back a victorious army, should have been given an audience
outside the walls, now, after slaughtering your own countrymen, and
stained with the blood of kinsmen, enter into the city with flying
flags. Amidst the ensigns of soldiers let Liberty be dumb,
and, now that all war has been banished afar, all terror suppressed,
let that people who conquered and pacified the nations of the earth
be beleaguered within its own walls, and shudder at the sight of its
own eagles.
Ungrateful is Coriolanus,/a who became dutiful too late, and after
penitence for crime; he laid down his arms, but he laid them down in
the midst of unholy war. Ungrateful is
Catiline; he is not satisfied with seizing his fatherland -he must
overturn it, he must let loose against it the cohorts of the
Allobroges, he must summon an enemy from beyond the Alps to satiate
its old and inborn hatred, and pay with the <Ess3-333>
ON BENEFITS, V. xvi. 1-4
lives of Roman leaders the sacrifices long
owed to Gallic tombs./a Ungrateful is Gaius Marius {Coriolanus?+}, who, though raised from the
rank of a common soldier to repeated consulships, will feel that the
change in his fortune has been too slight, and that he would sink to
his former position did he not match the slaughter of the Cimbrians
with a sacrifice of Roman lives, did he not; not merely give, but
himself become, the signal for the destruction and butchery of his
countrymen.
Ungrateful is Lucius Sulla, who healed his fatherland by remedies
that were harsher than her ills, who, having marched through human
blood all the way from the citadel of Praeneste to the Colline Gate,
staged other battles, other murders inside the city; two legions
that had been crowded into a corner he butchered; O! the cruelty of
it, after he had won the victory, O! the wickedness of it, after he
had promised them quarter; and he devised proscription, great gods!
in order that anyone who had killed a Roman citizen might claim
impunity, money, all but a civic crown! Ungrateful is Gnaeus
Pompeius, who in return for three consulships, in return for three
triumphs, in return for the many public offices into most of which
he had thrust himself before the legal age, showed such gratitude to
the commonwealth that he induced others/b also to lay hands upon her
- as if he could render his own power less odious by giving several
others the right to do what no man ought to have had the right to
do! While he coveted extraordinary commands, while he
distributed the provinces to suit his own choice, while he divided
the commonwealth in such a way, that though a third person/c had a
share, <Ess3-335>
ON BENEFITS, V. xvi. 4-xvii. 2
two-thirds of it remained in his own
family,a he reduced the Roman people to such a plight that only by
the acceptance of slavery were they able to survive. The foe
and conqueror/b of Pompeius was himself ungrateful. From Gaul and
Germany he whirled war to Rome, and that friend of the people, that
democrat, pitched his camp in the Circus Flaminius, even nearer to
the city than Porsina's had been. It is true that he used the
cruel privileges of victory with moderation; the promise that he was
fond of making he kept - he killed no man who was not in arms.
But what of it? The others used their arms more cruelly, yet,
once glutted, flung them aside; he quickly sheathed his sword, but
never laid it down. Ungrateful was Antony
to his dictator, who he declared was rightly slain,/c and whose
murderers he allowed to depart to their commands in the
provinces. His country, torn as it had been by proscriptions,
invasions, and wars, after all her ills, he wished to make subject
to kings, who were not even Roman, in order that a city that had
restored sovereign rights, autonomy, and immunity to the Achaeans,
the Rhodians, and many famous cities, might herself pay tribute to
eunuchs!/a The day
will fail me to enumerate those whose ingratitude resulted in the
ruin of their country. Equally endless will be the task if I
attempt a survey of how ungrateful the commonwealth herself has been
to its best and most devoted servants, and how it has sinned not
less often than it has been sinned against. Camillus it sent
into exile, Scipio went with its con- -------- a An allusion to the
Egyptian court and Antony+'s surrender to the charms
of Cleopatra. <Ess3-337>
ON BENEFITS, V. xvii. 2-5
sent; it exiled Cicero, even after the
conspiracy of Catiline, destroyed his home, plundered his property,
did everything that a victorious Catiline would have done;
Rutilius/a found his blamelessness rewarded with a hiding-place in
Asia; to Cato the Roman people refused the praetorship, and
persisted in refusing the consulship. We are universally
ungrateful. Let each one question himself - everyone will find
someone to complain of for being ungrateful. But it is
impossible that all men should complain, unless all men gave cause
for complaint - all men, therefore, are ungrateful. Are they
ungrateful only? They are also covetous and spiteful and
cowardly - especially those who appear to be bold. Besides,
all are self-seeking, all are ungodly. But you have no need to
be angry with them; pardon them - they are all mad. {Lear+} To refer you to uncertain
instances is not my desire, so I say: "See how ungrateful is
youth! What young man does not long for his father's last day
though his hands are clean? Does not look forward to it though
he curbs his desire? Does not ponder it though he is
dutiful? How few there are who dread so much the death of
their best of wives that they do not even calculate the
probabilities? What litigant, I ask you, after he has been
defended, retains the memory of so great a benefit beyond the hour
it happened?" And
all agree in asking who dies without complaint! Who on his last day
ventures to say:
I've lived; my destined
course I now have run. Who does not shrink from
departure? Who does not mourn it? Yet not to be
satisfied with the time <Ess3-339>
ON BENEFITS, V. xvii. 5-xviii. 2
one has had is to be ungrateful. Your
days will always seem few if you stop to count them. Reflect
that your greatest blessing does not lie in mere length of time;
make the best of it however short it may be. Though the day of
your death should be postponed, your happiness is in no whit
enhanced, since life becomes, not more blissful, but merely longer,
by the delay. How much better it is to be grateful for the
pleasures that have been enjoyed, not to reckon up the years of
others, but to set a generous value on one's own, and to score them
down as gain! "God deemed me worthy of this, this is enough;
he might have given more, but even this is a benefit." Let us be
grateful to the gods, grateful to mankind, grateful to those who
have bestowed anvthing, upon ourselves, grateful also to those who
have bestowed anything upon our dear ones. "You render me
liable," you retort, "to infinite obligation when you say 'also upon
our dear ones'; so do set some limit. According to you, he who
gives a benefit to a son, gives it also to his father. This is
the first question I raise. Secondly, I should like
particularly to have this point settled. If the benefit is
given also to your friend's father, is it given also to his
brother? Also to his uncle? Also to his
grandfather? Also to his wife? Also to his
father-in-law? Tell me, where must I stop, how far am I to pursue
the list of relatives?" If I cultivate your field, I shall give you
a benefit; if your house is on fire and I shall put it out, or if I
keep it from tumbling down, I shall give you a benefit; if I heal
your slave, I shall charge the service to you; if I save the life of
your son, will you not have a benefit from me? <Ess3-341>
ON BENEFITS, V. xix. 1-4
xxx"The instances you offer are of a
different colour, for he who cultivates my field, gives a benefit,
not to the field, but to me; and he who props up my house - to keep
it from falling, bestows a benefit on me, for the house itself is
without feeling; because it has none, he makes me his debtor; and he
who cultivates my field, wishes to do a service, not to it, but to
me. I should say the same of the slave, he is a chattel of
mine, it is to my advantage to have his life saved; therefore the
debt is mine instead of his. But my son is himself capable of
receiving a benefit; he, therefore, receives it, while I merely
rejoice, and, though I am nearly concerned, I am not placed under
obligation by it."
Nevertheless I should like you, who suppose that you are under no
obligation, to answer me this. A father is concerned in the
good health, the happiness, the inheritance of his son; he is going
to be made more happy if he keeps his son alive, more unhappy if he
has lost him. What, then? If anyone is made happier by
me, if he is freed from the danger of the greatest unhappiness, does
he not receive a benefit? "No," you answer, "for
there are some things that, though they are conferred upon others,
pass on to us; but, in each case, the thing ought to be required of
the one upon whom it was conferred, just as, in the case of a loan,
money is sought from the one to whom it was lent, although it may by
some means have come into my hands. There is no benefit whose
advantage does not extend to those who are nearest to the recipient,
sometimes even to those who are far removed; the question is, not
whither did the benefit pass from the one to whom it was given, but
where <Ess3-343>
ON BENEFITS, V. xix. 4-7
was it first placed. You must be
repaid by the real debtor, the one who first received it." What,
then? I beg of you, do you not say to me: "You have given me
the life of my son, and, if he had perished, I could not have
survived him"? Do you not owe a benefit in return for the life
of one whose safety you value above your own? Besides, when I
have saved your son's life, you fall upon your knees, you pay vows
to the gods just as if your own life had been saved; your lips utter
these words: "Whether you have saved my own life is to me of
no concern; you have saved both our lives - nay, rather, mine." Why
do vou say this if you do not receive a benefit? "Because, also, if my
son were to obtain a loan of money, I should pay his creditor, yet
should not for that reason be indebted to him; because also, if my
son should be caught in adultery, I should blush, yet should not for
that reason become an adulterer. I say that I am indebted to
you for my son's life, not because I really am, but because I wish
to constitute myself your debtor of my own free will. But his
safety has brought to me the greatest possible pleasure, the
greatest possible advantage, and I have escaped the heaviest of all
blows, the loss of a child. The question is now, not whether
you have been of service to me, but whether you have given me a
benefit; for a dumb animal, or a stone, or a plant, can be of
service, and yet they cannot give a benefit, for a benefit is never
given without an act of the will. But you wish to give, not to
the father, but to the son, and sometimes you do not even know the
father. Therefore, when you have said: 'Have I not, then,
given a benefit to the father by saving the life of his son?' you
must raise the counter-question: 'Have I, then, <Ess3-345>
ON BENEFITS, V. xix. 7-xx. 2
given a benefit to the father, whom I do not
know, of whom I had no thought?' And what if, as will sometimes
happen, you hate the father, yet save the life of his son?
Will you be considered to have given a benefit to one to whom, at
the very time that you gave it, you had the greatest hostility?"
But, to lay aside the bickering of dialogue, and to reply, as it
were, judicially, I should say that the purpose of the giver must be
considered; he gave the benefit to the one to whom he wished it to
be given. If he did it as a compliment to the father, then the
father received the benefit; if, as a service to the son, the father
is placed under no obligation by the benefit conferred upon the son,
even if he is pleased by it. If, however, he gets the
opportunity, he will himself wish to bestow something, not that he
feels the necessity of repaying, but that he finds an excuse for
offering a service. Repayment of the benefit must not be
sought from the father; if he does a generous act because of it, he
is, not grateful, but just. For there can be no end to it - if
I am giving a benefit to my friend's father, I am giving it also to
his mother, his grandfather, his uncle, his children, his relatives,
his friends, his slaves, his country. Where, then, does a
benefit begin to stop? For there enters in the endless
sorites,/a to which it is difficult to set any limit, for it grows
little by little, and never stops growing. This, too, is a
common question: "If two brothers are at variance, and I save
the life of one, do I give a benefit to the, other who will probably
regret that the brother he hated did not die?" There can be no doubt
that to render a service to a man even against his will is a
benefit, just as he who has rendered a service against his will has
not given a benefit. "Do <Ess3-347>
ON BENEFITS, V. xx. 2-5
you," you ask, "call that which vexes him,
which torments him a benefit?" Yes, many benefits are, on their
face, stern and harsh, such as the cures wrought by surgery and
cautery and confinement in chains. The point to consider is,
not whether anyone is made unhappy, but whether he ought to be made
happy, by receiving a benefit; a coin is not necessarily a bad one
because a barbarian who does not know the government stamp has
rejected it. A man both hates, and yet accepts, a benefit
provided that it does him good, provided that the giver gave it in
order that it might do him good. It makes no difference
whether anyone accepts a good thing with a bad spirit or not.
Come, consider the converse case. A man hates his brother, but
it is to his advantage to keep him; if I have killed the brother, I
do not do him a benefit, although he may say that it is, and be glad
of it. It is a very artful enemy who gets thanked for the
injury he has done! "I understand; a thing
that does good is a benefit, a thing that does harm is not a
benefit. But see here, I will give you an instance where
neither good nor harm is done, and yet the act will be a
benefit. Suppose I have found the corpse of someone's father
in a lonely place, and bury it. I have done no good either to
the man himself (for what difference would it make to him in what
fashion he rotted?), or to the son (for what advantage does he gain
by the act?)." I
will tell you what he has gained. Using me as his instrument,
he has performed a customary and necessary duty; I supplied to his
father what he would have wished, what it would also have been his
duty, to supply himself. Yet such an act becomes a benefit
only if I performed it, not out of the sense <Ess3-349>
ON BENEFITS, V. xx. 5-7
of pity and humanity that would lead me to
hide away anybody's corpse, but because I recognized the body, and
supposed that I was rendering a service to the son. But, if I
have thrown earth over an unknown dead man, I have by the act made
no one my debtor for this service - I am just generally
humane. But some one will say: "Why do vou take so much
trouble to discover to whom you should give a benefit as though you
intended to ask repayment some day? There are some who think
that repayment ought never to be asked, and the reasons they adduce
are these. An unworthy person will not make return even when
he is asked to do so, and the worthy man will repay of his own
accord. Moreover, if you have given to a good man, be patient;
do not do him an injustice by dunning him, as though he would not
have made return of his own accord. If you have given to a bad
man, you must blame yourself; but do not spoil a benefit by making
it a loan. Besides, the law, by not bidding you to ask
repayment, forbids you." These are mere words. So long as I
have no pressing need, so long as I am not foreed by fortune, I
would rather lose a benefit than ask for repayment. If,
however, the safety of my children is at stake, if my wife is
threatened with danger, if the safety of my country and my liberty
impel me to a course that I should prefer not to take, I shall
conquer my scruples, and bear witness that I have done everything to
avoid needing the help of an ungrateful person; the necessity of
receiving a return of my benefit will at last overcome my reluctance
to ask a return. Again, when I give a benefit to a good man, I
do so with the intention of never asking a return unless it should
be necessary. <Ess3-351>
ON BFNFFITS, V. xxi. 1-xxii. 1
xxx"But," you say, "the law, by not
authorizing, forbids the exaction." There are many things that do
not come under the law or into court, and in these the conventions
of human life, that are more binding than anylaw+, show us
the way. No law forbids us to divulge the secrets of friends;
no law bids us keep faith even with an enemy. What law binds
us to keep a promise that we have made to anyone? There is
none. Yet I shall have a grievance against a person who has
not kept the secret I told him, and I shall be indignant with one
who, after giving a promise, has not kept it. "But," you say, "you
are turning a benefit into a loan." By no means; for I do not
demand, but request, and I do not even request, but simply
remind. Shall even the most pressing necessity ever force me
to go to one with whom there would be need for me to have a long
struggle? If anyone is so ungrateful that a simple reminder
will not suffice, I shall pass him by, and judge him unworthy of
being compelled to be grateful. As a money-lender makes no
demand of certain debtors who he knows have become bankrupt, and, to
their shame, have nothing left but what is already lost, so I shall
pass over certain men who are openly and obstinately ungrateful, and
I shall ask a benefit to be repaid by no one from whom I could not
hope, not to extort, but to receive, a return. There are many
who do not know how either to disavow or to repay what they have
received, who are neither good enough to be grateful, nor bad enough
to be ungrateful - slow and dilatory people, backward debtors, but
not defaulters. Of these I shall make no demand, but shall admonish
them and turn them back from other interests to their duty.
They will promptly <Ess3-353>
ON BENEFITS, V. xxii. 1-xxiii. 1
reply to me: "Pardon me; upon my word,
I did not know that you missed the money, or I would have offered it
of my own accord; I beg you not to think me ungrateful; I am mindful
of your favour to me." Why should I hesitate to make such as these
better men both in their own eyes and in mine? If can keep
anyone from doing, wrong, I shall; much more a friend - both from
doing wrong and, most of all, from doing wrong to me. I bestow
a second benefit upon him by, not permitting him to be ungrateful;
nor will I reproach him harshly with what I had bestowed, but as
gently as I can. In order to give him an opportunity to show
his gratitude, I shall refresh his memory, and ask for a benefit; he
will himself understand that I am asking repayment. Sometimes if l
have hope of being able to correct his fault, I shall use harsher
words; yet, if he is beyond hope, I shall not exasperate him as
well, for fear that I may turn an ingrate into an enemy. But
if we spare ungrateful men even the affront of an admonition, we
shall make them more dilatory in returning benefits. Some,
indeed, who are curable, if conscience pricks them, and might become
good men will be left to go to ruin if we withhold the admonition by
which a father at times reclaims his son, by which a wife brings
back to her arms an erring husband, and a friend stimulates the
flagging loyalty of a friend. In order to awaken some men, it
is necessary only to shake, not to strike, them; in the same way, in
the case of some men, their sense of honour about returning
gratitude is, not extinct, but only asleep. {Bassanio+} Let
us arouse it. "Do not," they might say, "turn your gift into
an injury; for injury it will be if you fail to ask repayment for
the express purpose of leaving me ungrateful. What if I do not
know what you desire? <Ess3-355>
ON BENEFITS, V. xxiii. 1-xxiv. 2
What if I have not watched for an
opportunity because I was distracted by business+ and
occupied with other interests? Show me what I can do, what you
wish me to do. Why do you lose faith before you put me to the
test? Why are you in a hurry to lose both your benefit and a
friend? How do you know whether I am unwilling, or merely
unaware - whether I am lacking in opportunity, or intention?
Give me a chance!" I shall, therefore, remind him of my benefit, not
bitterly, not publicly, not with reproaches, but in such a way that
he will think that, instead of being brought back, he himself has
come back, to the recollection of it. One of his veterans,
being greatly incensed against his neighbours, was once pleading his
case before the deified Julius, and the case was going against
him. "Do you remember, general" he said, "the time in Spain
when you sprained your ankle near the river Sucro?" When Caesar
replied that he remembered it, he continued: "Do you remember,
too, when, because of the powerful heat of the sun, you wanted to
rest under a certain tree that cast very little shade, that one of
your fellow-soldiers spread out his cloak for you because the
ground, in which that solitary tree had sprung up among the sharp
stones, was very rough?" When Caesar replied: "Of course I do;
and, too, when I was perishing with thirst, and wanted to crawl to a
nearby spring because, crippled as I was, I could not walk, unless
my companion, who was a strong and active man, had brought me some
water in his helmet - " "Could you, then, general," interrupted the
veteran, "recognize that man, or that helmet?" Caesar replied that
he could not recognize the helmet, but that he could the man, <Ess3-357>
ON BENEFITS, V. xxxv. 2-xxv. 2
perfectly, and, irritated I suppose because
he allowed himself to revert to the old incident in the midst of a
trial, added: "You, at any rate, are not the one." "You have
good reason, Caesar," he replied, "not to recognize me; for, when
this happened, I was a whole man; later, during the battle of Munda,
one of my eyes was torn out, and some bones were taken from my
skull. And you would not recognize that helmet if you saw it;
for it was split by a Spanish sword." Caesar gave orders that the
man was not to be troubled, and presented his old soldier with the
bit of ground which, because his neighbours made a path through it,
had been the cause of the quarrel and the suit. What, then?
Because his commander's memory of a benefit he received had been
dimmed by a multitude of happenings, and his position as the
organizer of vast armies did not permit him to meet individual
soldiers, should the veteran not have asked him to return the
benefit he had conferred? This is, not so much asking for the
repayment of a benefit, as taking repayment when it lies waiting in
a convenient place, although one must stretch forth one's hand in
order to take it. I shall, therefore, ask for repayment, when either
the pressure of great necessity, or the best interest of him from
whom I am asking it shall urge me to do so. Tiberius Caesar, when
a certain man started to say "You remember - ," interrupted him
before he could reveal more evidence of an old intimacy with:
"I do not remember what I was." Why should he not have been asked to
repay a benefit? He had a reason for desiring forgetfulness;
he was repudiating the acquaintance of all friends and comrades, and
<Ess3-359>
ON BENEFITS, V. xxv. 2-6
wished men to behold only the high position
he then filled, to think and to talk only of that. He regarded
an old friend as an accuser! xxx It is even more needful to choose
the right time for requesting the return of a benefit than for
requesting its bestowal. We must be temperate in our language,
so that the grateful man may not take offence, nor the ungrateful
pretend to do so. If we lived among wise men, it would have
been our duty to keep silence and wait; and yet it would have been
better to indicate even to wise men what the condition of our
affairs demanded. We petition even the gods, whose knowledge
nothing escapes, and, although our prayers do not prevail upon them,
they remind them of us. Homer's priest,/a I say, recounts even
to the gods his services and his pious care of their altars. The
second best form of virtue is to be willing and able to take
advice./b The horse that is docile and obedient can easily be turned
hither and thither by a gentle movement of the reins. Few men
follow reason as their best guide; next best are those who return to
the right path when they are admonished; these must not be deprived
of their guide. The eyes, even when they are closed, still
have the power of sight, but do not use it; but the light of day,
when it has been admitted to them, summons their power of sight into
service. Tools lie idle unless the workman uses them to
perform his task. Our minds all the while possess the virtuous
desire, but it lies torpid, now from their softness and disuse, now
from their ignorance of duty. We ought to render this desire
useful, and, instead of abandoning it in vexation to its weakness,
we should bear with it as patiently as schoolmasters bear with the
blunders of young pupils <Ess3-361>
ON BENEFITS, V. xxv. 6
when their memory fails; and, just as one or
two words of prompting will bring back to their memory the context
of the speech they must deliver, so the virtuous desire needs some
reminder to recall it to the repayment of gratitude.
<Ess3-363>
BOOK VI
THERE are some matters, my most excellent
Liberalis, that are investigated simply for the sake of exercising
the intellect, and lie altogether outside of life; others that are a
source of pleasure while the investigation is in progress, and of
profit when it is finished. I shall lay the whole store of
them before you; do you, as you may feel inclined, order me either
to discuss them at length, or merely to present them in order to
show the programme of the entertainment. But something will be
gained even from those which you may order to be at once dismissed:
for there is some advantage in discovering even what is not worth
learning, I shall, therefore, watch the expression of your face,
and, according as it guides me, deal with some questions at greater
length, and pitch others headlong out of court. The question has been
raised whether it is possible to take away a benefit. Some say
that it is not possible, for a benefit is, not a thing, but an
act. As a gift is one thing, the act of giving another, as a
sailor is one thing, the act of sailing another, and, as a sick man
and his disease are not the same thing although a sick man is not
without discase, so a benefit is one thing, and that which anyone
receives by means of the benefit another, the benefit is
incorporeal, and is never rendered invalid; the matter of it is
passed <Ess3-365>
ON BENEFITS, VI. ii. 2-iii. 2
from hand to hand, and changes its
owner. And so, when you take this away, even Nature herself is
not able to recall what she has once given./a She may break off her
benefits, she cannot annul them; he who dies has nevertheless lived;
he who has lost his eyes has nevertheless seen. Blessings that
we have received can cease to be ours, but they can never cease from
having been ours; what has been, too, is part of a benefit, and,
indeed, its surest part. Sometimes we are kept from very long
enjoyment of a benefit, but the benefit itself is not
obliterated. Nature is not allowed to reverse her acts, though
she should summon all her powers to the task. A man's house,
his money, his property, everything that passes under the name of a
benefit, may be taken away from him, but the benefit itself remains
fixed and unmoved; no power can efface the fact that this man has
given, and that one received. Those seem to me noble
words, which in the poet Rabirius/b are ascribed to Mark
Antony+, when, seeing his fortune deserting him, and nothing
left him but the privilege of dying, and even that on the condition
of his seizing it promptly, he is made to exclaim:
Whatever I have given+, that
I still possess {Akumal+} O! how much he might
have possessed if he had wished! These are the riches that
will abide, and remain steadfast amid all the fickleness of our
human lot; and, the greater they become, the less envy they will
arouse. Why do vou share your wealth as though it were your
own? You are but a steward. {trustee+} All these possessions
that force you to swell with pride, and, exalting you above mortals,
cause you to <Ess3-367>
ON BENEFITS, VI. iii. 2-iv. i
forget your own frailty; all these that you
guard with iron bars and watch under arms; stolen from others at the
cost of their blood, you defend at the cost of your own; these for
which you launch fleets to dye the sea with blood; these for which
you shatter cities to destruction, uncomncsious of how many arrows
of Fortune you may be preparing for you behind your back; these for
which you have so many times violated the ties of kinship, and of
partnership, while the whole world lies crushed amid the rivalry of
two contestants - all these are not your own. They are
committed to your safe keeping. and at any moment may find another
guardian; your enemy will seize upon them, or the heir who accounts
you an enemy. Do you ask how you can make them your own?
By bestowing them as gifts! Do you therefore, make the best of
your possessions, and, by making therm, not only safer, but more
honourable, render your own claim to them assured and inviolable.
The wealth that you esteem, that, as you think, makes you rich and
powerful, is buried under an inglorious name so long as you keep
it. It is but house, or slave, or money; when you have given
it away, it is a benefit. "You admit," says
someone, "that there are times when we are under no obligation to
the man from whom we have received a benefit; it has, therefore,
been taken away." There are many things that might cause us to cease
to feel indebted for a benefit, not because it has been removed, but
because it has been ruined. Suppose a man defends me in a
lawsuit, but has forced my wife to commit adultery; he has not
removed his benefit, but has freed me from indebtedness by matching
his benefit <Ess3-369>
ON BENEFITS, VI. iv. 1-5
with an equally great wrong, and, if he has
injured me more than he had previously benefited me, he not only
extinguishes my gratitude, but leaves me free to protest and avenge
myself whenever, in balancing the two, the wrong outweighs the
benefit; thus the benefit is not withdrawn, but is surpassed.
Tell me, are not some fathers so harsh and so wicked that it is
right and proper to turn away from them and disown them? Have
they, then, withdrawn the benefits that they had given? By no
means, but their unfeeling conduct in later years has removed the
favour that they had won from all their earlier service. It is
not the benefit, but gratitude for the benefit, that is removed, and
the result is, not that I do not possess it, but that I am under no
obligation for it. It is just as if someone should lend me
money, and then set fire to my house. The loan has been
balanced by my loss; I have made him no return, and yet I owe him
nothing. In the same way, too, a man who has acted kindly and
generously toward me, yet later has shown himself in many ways
haughty, insulting, and cruel, places me in the position of being
just as free from any obligation to him as if I had never received
anything; he has murdered his benefits. Though the lease remains in
force, a landlord has no claim against his tenant if he tramples
upon his crops, if he cuts down his orchard; not because he received
the payment agreed upon, but because he has made it impossible to
receive it. So, too, a creditor is often adjudged to his
debtor, when on some other account he has robbed him of more than he
claims on account of the loan. It is not merely the creditor
and debtor who have a judge to sit between them, and say: "You
lent the man <Ess3-371>
ON BENEFITS, VI. iv. 5-v. 3
money. Very well, then! But you
drove off his flock, you killed his slave, you have in your
possession silver that you did not buy; having calculated the value
of these, you who came into court as a creditor, must leave it as a
debtor." So, too, a balance is struck between benefits and
injuries. Often, I say, the benefit endures, and yet imposes
no obligation. If the giver repents of his gift, if he says that he
is sorry that he gave it, if he sighs, or makes a wry face when he
gives it, if he thinks that he is, not bestowing, but throwing away,
his gift, if he gave it to please himself, or, at any rate, not to
please me, if he persists in being offensive, in boasting of his
gift, in bragging of it everywhere, and in making it painful to me,
the benefit endures, although it imposes no obligation, just as
certain sums of money to which a creditor can establish no legal
right may be owed to him though he cannot demand them. You
have bestowed a benefit upon me, yet afterwards you did me an
injury; the reward of a benefit should be gratitude, of an injury
punishment; but I do not owe you gratitude, nor do you owe me my
revenge - the one is absolved by the other. When we say:
"I have returned to him his benefit," we mean that we have returned,
not the actual gift that we had received, but something else in its
place. For to return is to give one thing in return for
another; evidently so, since in every act of repayment we return,
not the same object, but the same value. For we are said to
have returned money even though we count out gold coins for silver,
and, even though no money passes between us, payment may be effected
by the assignment of a debt and orally. xxx I think I hear you
saying: "You are wasting your <Ess3-373>
ON BENEFITS, VI. v. 3-vi. I
time; for what is the use of my knowing
whether the benefit that imposes no obligation remains a
benefit. This is like the clever stupidities of lawyers, who
declare that one can take possession, not of an inheritance, but
only of the objects that are included in the inheritance, just as if
there were any difference between an inheritance and the objects
that are included in an inheritance./a Do you, instead, make clear
for me this point, which may be of some practical use. When
the same man has bestowed on me a benefit, and has afterwards done
me an injury, ought I to return to him the benefit, and nevertheless
to avenge myself upon him, and to make reply, as it were, on two
distinct scores, or ought I to combine the two into one, and take no
action at all, leaving the benefit to be wiped out by the injury,
and the injury be the benefit? For this is what I see is the
practice of our courts; you Stoics should know what the law is in
your school. In the courts the processes are kept separate,
and the case that I have against another and the case that another
has against me are not merged under one formula. If anyone
deposits a sum of money in my safekeeping, and the same man
afterwards steals something from me, I shall proceed against him for
theft, and he will proceed against me for the money deposited." The instances that you
have set forth, Liberalis, come under fixed laws, which we are bound
to follow. One law does not merge into another law; each
proceeds along its own way. A particular action deals with a
deposit, and just as clearly another deals with theft. But a
benefit is subject to no law, it makes me the judge. I have
the right to compare the amount of good or the amount of harm anyone
may have <Ess3-375>
ON BENEFITS, VI. vi. 1-vii. 2
done me, and then to decide whether he is
more indebted to me, or I to him. In legal actions we
ourselves have no power, we must follow the path by which we are
led; in the case of a benefit I have all the power, I render
judgement. And so I make no separation or distinction between
benefits and injuries, but commit them both to the same judge.
Otherwise, you force me to love and to hate, and to complain and to
give thanks, at the same time; but this is contrary to nature.
Instead, after making a comparison of benefit and injury, I shall
discover whether there is still any balance in my favour. As,
if anyone imprints other lines of writing upon my manuscript, he
conceals, though he does not remove, the letters that were there
before, so an injury that comes on top of a benefit does not allow
the benefit to be seen. Your face, by which I
agreed to be guided, is now puckered and frowning, as though I were
straying too far afield. You seem to me to be saying:
Whither so far to the
right? Port your helm Hug the
shore./a <Aeneid> I cannot more closely. So
now, if you think that I have exhausted this question, let me pass
to the next one - whether anyone who does us a service without
wishing to, imposes any obligation upon us. I might have
expressed this more clearly, but the proposition had to be stated
somewhat obscurely in order that it might be shown by the
distinction immediately following that two questions are involved -
both whether we are under any obligation to a man who does us a
service against his will, and whether we are under obligation to one
who does us a service without knowing it. For why a man does
not place us under <Ess3-377>
ON BENEFITS, VI. vii. 2-4
obligation if he has done us some favour
because he was foreed to is so clear that no words need to be
devoted to it. Both this question and any similar one that can
be raised will be easily settled if in every case we direct our
attention to the thought that a benefit is always something that is
conveyed to us, in the first place, by some intent, in the second
place, by some intent that is kind and friendly. Consequently
we do not expend our thanks upon rivers even though they may bear
large ships, flow in copious and unfailing stream for the conveyance
of merchandise, or wind beauteously and full of fish through the
rich farm-lands. And no one conceives of himself as being
indebted for a benefit to the Nile, any more than he would owe it a
grudge if it overflowed its banks immoderately, and was slow in
retiring; the wind does not bestow a benefit, even though its blast
is gentle and friendly, nor does wholesome and serviceable
food. For he who would give me a benefit must not only do, but
wish to do, me a service. We, therefore, become indebted neither to
dumb animals - and yet how many men have been rescued from peril by
the speed of a horse! nor to trees -and yet how many toilers have
been sheltered from the summer's heat by the shade of their
boughs! But what difference does it make whether I have
received a service from someone who did not know, or from someone
who was not able to know, that he was doing it if in both cases the
desire to do it was lacking? What difference is there between
expecting me to feel indebted for a benefit to a ship or to a
carriage or to a spear, and expecting me to feel indebted to a man
who had just as little intention as they of performing a good act,
yet chanced to do me a service? <Ess3-379>
ON BENEFITS, VI. viii. 1-4
Anyone
can receive, but no one can bestow, a benefit without knowing
it. Many sick persons are cured by chance happenings that are
not for that reason to be counted remedies, and a man's falling into
a river in very cold weather has restored him to health; some have
had a quartan fever broken by a flogging, and the dangerous hours
passed unnoticed because their sudden fear diverted their attention
to another trouble, and yet none of these things are for that reason
to be counted salutary, even if they have restored health. In
like manner, certain persons do us service while they are unwilling,
nay, because they are unwilling; and yet they do not for that reason
make us indebted for a benefit, because it was Fortune that turned
their harmful designs into good. Do you think that I am under
any obligation to a man whose hand struck my enemy when it was aimed
at me, who, unless he had blundered, would have done me an
injury? Often a witness, by openly perjuring himself, causes
even truthful witnesses to be disbelieved, and yet arouses
compassion for the man under accusation because he seems to be beset
by a conspiracy. Some men have been saved by the very power that was
exerted to crush them, and judges, who were about to convict a man
on the score of his case have refused to convict him on the score of
influence./a Yet, although the great men did him a service, it was
not a benefit that they bestowed upon the accused, because it is a
question of, not what the dart hits, but what it was aimed at, and
it is, not the result, but the intention,that distinguishes a
benefit from an injury. My opponent, by contradicting the
judge, by offending him by his arrogance, and by rashly reducing his
case <Ess3-381>
ON BENEFITS, VI. viii. 4-x. 1
to one witness, advanced my cause; I do not
consider whether his mistake helped me - he meant to do me harm. Of course, in order to
show gratitude to benefactor, I must wish to do the same thing that
he must have wished in order to give a benefit to me. Can
anything be more unjust than to hate a person who has trodden upon
your foot in a crowd, or splashed you, or shoved you where you did
not wish to go? Yet, since he actually does us an injury, what
besides the fact that he did not know what he was doing exempts him
from blame? The same reason keeps this man from having given
us a benefit, and that one from having done us an injury; it is the
intention that makes both the friend and the enemy. How many
have escaped military service because of sickness! Some have
escaped from sharing the destruction of their house by being forced
by an enemy to appear in court, some have escaped falling into the
hands of pirates by having met with shipwreck; yet such happenings
do not impose the obligation of a benefit, because chance has no
sense of the service rendered, nor does an enemy, whose lawsuit,
while it harassed and detained us, saved our lives. Nothing
can be a benefit that does not proceed from goodwill, that is not
recognized as such by the one who gives it. Someone did me a
service without knowing it - I am under no obligation to him.
Someone did me a service when he wished to injure me - I will
imitate him! Let
us revert to the first type. Would you have me do something in
order to show my gratitude? But he himself did nothing in
order to give me a benefit! Passing to the second type, do you
wish me to show <Ess3-383>
ON BENEFITS, VI. x. i-xi. 3
gratitude to such a man - of my own will to
return what I received from him against his will? And what
shall I say of the third type, the man who stumbled into doing a
benefit in trying to do an injury? To render me indebted to
you for a benefit, it is not enough that you wished to give; but, to
keep me from being indebted to you, it is enough that you did not
wish to give. For a benefit is not accomplished by a mere
wish; but, because the best and most copious wish would not be a
benefit if good fortune had been lacking, just as truly good fortune
is not a benefit unless the good wish has preceded the good
fortune. For in order to place me under obligation to you, you
must not merely have done me a service, but have done it
intentionally.
Cleanthes makes use of the following example. "I sent," he says,
"two lads to look for Plato and bring him to me from the
Academy. One of them searched through the whole colonnade, and
also hunted through other places in which he thought that he might
be found, but returned home alike weary and unsuccessful; the other
sat down to watch a mountebank near by, and, while amusing himself
in company with other slaves, the careless vagabond found Plato
without looking for him, as he happened to pass by. The first
lad, he says, will have our praise, for, to the best of his ability,
he did what he had been ordered; the fortunate idler we shall flog."
It is the desire
that, according to us, establishes the service; and consider what
the terms are if you would place me under obligation. It is
not enough for a man to have the wish without having done a service;
it is not enough to have done a service <Ess3-385>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xi. 3-xii. 2
without having had the wish. For
suppose that someone wished to make a gift, but did not make it; I
have, it is true, the intention, but I do not have the benefit, for
its consummation requires both an object and an intention.
Just as I owe nothing to a man who wished to lend me money, but did
not supply it, so, if a man wished to give me a benefit, but was not
able to do so, though I shall remain a friend, I shall be under no
obligation to him; and I shall wish to bestow something upon him
(for he wished to bestow something on me), but, if, having enjoyed
better fortune than he, I shall have succeeded in bestowing it, I
shall not be returning gratitude, but shall be giving him a
benefit. What he will owe me will be the repayment of
gratitude; the favour will begin with me, it will be counted from
me. I already know
what you wish to ask; there is no need for you to say anything; your
countenance speaks for you. "If anyone has done us a service
for his own sake, are we," you ask, "under any obligation to
him? For I often hear you complain that there are some things
that men bestow upon themselves, but charge them up to others." I
will tell you, Liberalis; but first let me break up that question,
and separate what is fair from what is unfair. For it makes a
great difference whether anyone gives us a benefit for his own sake,
or for his own sake and ours. He who looks wholly to his own
interest, and does us a service only because he could not otherwise
do himself a service, seems to me to be in a class with the man who
provides food for his flock summer and winter; in a class with the
man who, in order that he may sell his captives to greater
advantage, feeds them, stuffs them as fat as oxen, and rubs them
down; in a class <Ess3-387>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xii. 2-xiii. 4
with the fencing-master who takes the
greatest pains in training and equipping his troop of
gladiators. There is a great difference, as Cleanthes says,
between benefaction and trade. On the other hand, I
am not so unjust as to feel under no obligation to a man who, when
he was profitable to me, was also profitable to himself. For I
do not require that he should consult my interests without any
regard to his own, nay, I am also desirous that a benefit given to
me should be even more advantageous to the giver, provided that,
when he gave it, he was considering us both, and meant to divide it
between himself and me. Though he should possess the larger
part of it, provided that he allowed me to share in it, provided
that he considered both of us, I am, not merely unjust, I am
ungrateful, if I do not rejoice that, while he has benefited me, he
has also benefited himself. It is supreme niggardliness to say
that nothing can be a benefit that does not inflict some hardship
upon the giver of it. To one of the other
type, the man who gives a benefit for his own sake only, I shall
reply: "Having made use of me, why have you any more right to
say that you have been of service to me, than I have to you?"
"Suppose," he retorts," that the only way in which I can obtain a
magistracy is to ransom ten out of a great number of captive
citizens; will you owe me nothing when I have freed you from bondage
and chains? Yet I shall do that for my own sake only." To this
I reply: "In this case vou are acting partly for your own
sake, partly for mine - for your own, in paying the ransom, for
mine, in paying a ransom for me. For you would have served
your own interests sufficiently by ransoming any you chose. <Ess3-389>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xiii. 4-xiv. 4
I am, therefore, indebted to you, not
because you ransom me, but because you choose me; for you might have
attained the same thing by ransoming someone else instead of
me. You divide the advantage of your act with me, and you
permit me to share in a benefit that will be of profit to both of
us. You prefer me to others; all this you do for my sake only.
if, therefore, you would be made praetor by ransoming ten captives,
and there were only ten of us in captivity, no one of us would owe
you anything, for you would have nothing apart from your own
advantage which you could charge up to anyone of us. I do not
regard a benefit jealously, nor desire that the whole of it should
be given to me, but,I desire a part." "That, then," he
replies, "if I had committed your names to a choice by lot, and your
name had appeared among those to be ransomed, would you owe nothing
to me?" Yes, I should owe something, but very little; just how much,
I will tell you. In that case you do something for my sake, in
that you admit me to the chance of being ransomed. I owe it to
Fortune that my name was drawn; I owe it to you that my name could
be drawn. You gave me the opportunity to share in your
benefit, for the greater part of which I am indebted to Fortune; but
I am indebted to you for the fact that I was able to become indebted
to Fortune. I shall wholly omit notice of those who make
benefaction mercenary, for he who gives in this spirit takes count
of, not to whom, but on what terms, he will give a benefit that is
wholly directed to his own interest. Someone sells me grain; I
cannot live unless I buy it; yet I do not owe my life to him because
I bought it. And I consider, not how <Ess3-391>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xiv. 4-xv. 4
necessary the thing was without which I
could not have lived, but how little gratitude I owe for something
that I should not have had unless I had bought it, in the
transportation of which the trader thought, not of how much help he
would bring to me, but of how much gain he would bring to
himself. What I have paid for entails no obligation. "According to that,"
you say, "you would claim that you are under no obligation to your
physician beyond his paltry fee, nor to your teacher, because you
have paid him some money. Yet for all these we have great
affection, great respect." The answer to this is that the price paid
for some things does not represent their value. You pay a
physician for what is invaluable, life and good health, a teacher of
the liberal sciences for the training of a gentleman and cultivation
of the mind. Consequently the money paid to these is the
price, not of their gift, but of their devotion in serving us, in
putting aside their own interests and giving their time to us; they
get paid, not for their worth, but for their trouble. Yet I
might more truly make another statement, which I shall at once
present, having first pointed out how your quibble can be refuted.
"If," you say, "the value of some things is greater than the price
they cost, then, although you have paid for them, you still owe me
something besides." But, in the first place, what difference does it
make what they are really worth, since the seller and the buyer have
agreed upon their price? In the second place, I bought the
thing, not at its own value, but at your price. "It is," you
retort, "worth more than it costs." Yes, but it could not have been
sold for more. Besides, the price of everything varies with
circumstances; <Ess3-393>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xv. 4-xvi. 1
though vou have well praised your wares,
they are worth only the highest price at which they can be sold; a
man, therefore, who buys them cheap, owes nothing more to the
seller. Again, even if they are worth more, nevertheless the
fact that their price is determined, not by their utility or
efficacy, but by the customary rate of the market, does not imply
that there is any gift on your part. At what would you value
the service of the man who crosses the seas, and, when he has lost
sight of the land, traces an unerring course through the midst of
the waves, who forecasts coming storms, and suddenly orders the
crew, when they have no sense of danger, to furl the sails, to lower
the tackle, and to stand ready to meet the assault and sudden fury
of the storm? Yet this man's reward for such great service is
paid by the passenger's fare! What value do you set on finding
lodging in a wilderness, a shelter in rain, a warm bath or a fire in
cold weather? Yet I know at what price I can obtain these
things when I enter an inn! How great a service does he do us
who props up our tottering house, and with unbelievable skill keeps
erect a group of buildings that are showing cracks at the
bottom! Yet a contract for underpinning is made at a fixed and
cheap rate. The city wall provides us protection from the
enemy and from the sudden attacks of brigands; yet it is well known
how much a workman is paid each day for erecting the towers provided
with parapets to assure the public safety. My task would be
endless if I tried to collect more instances to prove that valuable
things are sold at a low price. What, then? Why is it
that I owe something more to my physician and my teacher, and yet
<Ess3-395>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xvi, 1-5
do not complete the payment of what is due
to them? Because from being physician and teacher they pass
into friends, and we are under obligation to them, not because of
their skill, which they sell, but because of their kindly and
friendly goodwill. If, therefore, a physician does nothing
more than feel my pulse, and put me on the list of those whom he
visits in his rounds, instructing me what to do or to avoid without
any personal feeling, I owe him nothing more than his fee, because
he views me, not as a friend, but as a commander./a Nor is there any
reason why I should venerate a teacher if he has considered me
merely one of his many pupils, and has not deemed me worthy of any
particular and special consideration, if he has not directed his
attention to me, but has allowed me, not so much to learn from him,
as to pick up any knowledge that he spilled into our midst.
What reason, then, do we have for being much indebted to them?
It is, not that what they have sold is worth more than we paid for
it, but that they have contributed something to us personally.
Suppose a physician gave me more attention than was professionally
necessary; that it was, not for his professional reputation, but for
me, that he feared; that he was not content to indicate remedies,
but also applied them; that he sat at my bedside among my anxious
friends, that he hurried to me at the crises of my illness; that no
service was too burdensome, none too distasteful for him to perform;
that he was not indifferent when he heard my moans; that, though a
host of others called for him, I was always his chief concern; that
he took time for others only when my illness had permitted him -
such a man has placed me under obligation, not as a physician, but
as a friend. <Ess3-397>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xvi. 6-xviii. 1
Suppose, again, that the other endured
labour and weariness in teaching me; that, besides the ordinary
sayings of teachers, there are things which he has transmitted and
instilled into me; that by his encouragement he aroused the best
that was in me, at one time inspirited me by his praise, at another
warned me to put aside sloth; that, laying hand, so to speak, on my
mental powers that then were hidden and inert, he drew them forth
into the light; that, instead of doling out his knowledge grudgingly
in order that there might be the longer need of his service, he was
eager, if he could, to pour the whole of it into me - if I do not
owe to such a man all the love that I give to those to whom I am
bound by the most grateful ties, I am indeed ungrateful. If the hawkers of even
the meanest forms of service seem to us to have put forth unusual
effort, we give them something besides what we have agreed upon; we
dispense gratuities to a pilot, to a man who works with the
commonest material, and to one who hires out his services by the
day. Surely, in the case of the noblest professions that
either maintain or beautify life, a man is ungrateful if he thinks
that he owes no more than he bargained for. Add, too, that in
the transmission of such knowledge mind is fused with mind;
therefore, when this happens, to the teacher, and to the physician
as well, is paid the price of his service, but the price of his mind
is still owed. Once when Plato had been put across a river in
a boat, and found that the ferryman asked for no pay, thinking that
he had been shown a special compliment, said that the ferryman had
placed Plato under obligation to him. But a little later, when
he saw him just as zealously convey one after another <Ess3-399>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xviii. 1-xix. 4
across without any charge, he denied that
the ferryman had placed Plato under any obligation to him.
For, if you wish me to feel indebted for something that you bestow,
you must bestow it, not merely upon me, but because of me; you
cannot dun any man for the dole that you fling to the crowd.
What, then? Will no one owe you anything in return for
it? No one as an individual; the debt that I owe in company
with all I shall pay in company with all. "Do you say," you ask,
"that a man who has carried me across the river Po in a boat without
charge gives me no benefit?" I do. He does me a good turn, but
he does not give me a benefit; for he does it for his own sake, or,
at any rate, not for mine. In short, even the man himself does
not suppose that he is giving a benefit to me, but he bestows it for
the sake of the state, or of the neighbourhood, or of his own
ambition, and in return for it he expects some sort of advantage
quite different from that which he might receive from individual
passengers. "What, then," you say, "if the emperor should
grant citizenship to all the Gauls, and exemption from taxes to all
the Spaniards, would the individual on account of that owe him
nothing?" Of course he would owe something, but he would owe it, not
because of a personal benefit, but because of his share in a public
benefit. "The emperor," he says, "had no thought of me at the time
when he benefited us all; he did not desire to give citizenship to
me personally, nor did he direct his attention to me; so why should
I feel indebted to one who did not put me before himself when he was
thinking of doing what he did?" In the first place, when he planned
to benefit all the Gauls, he planned <Ess3-401>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xlx. 4-xx. 2
to benefit me also; for I was a Gaul, and
under my national, even if not under my personal, designation he
included me. In the second place, I shall, in like manner, be
indebted to him as having received, not a personal, but a general,
gift; being one of the people, I shall not pay the debt as one
incurred by myself, but shall contribute to it as one incurred by my
country. If anyone should lend money to my country, I should
not call myself his debtor, nor should I declare this as my debt
when a candidate for office or a defendant in a suit/a; yet I will
pay my share toward quashing the indebtedness. So I deny that
a gift which is given to an entire people makes me a debtor,
because, while it was given to me, it was not given because of me,
and, while it was given to me, the giver was not aware that he was
giving to me; nevertheless I shall be aware that I must pay
something for the gift, because after a roundabout course it arrived
also at me. An act that lays me under obligation must have been done
because of me.
"According to that," you say, "you are under no obligation to the
sun or to the moon; for they do not perform their movements solely
because of you." But, since the purpose of their movements is to
preserve the universe, they perform their movements for my sake
also; for I am a part of the universe. And besides, our
position is different from theirs; for he who does me a service in
order that by means of me he may do himself a service, has not given
a benefit, because he has made me an instrument for his own
advantage. But in the case of the sun and the moon, even if
they do us a service for their own sake, yet their purpose in doing
the service is not that by <Ess3-403>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xx. 2-xxi. 4
means of us they may do themselves a
service; for what is there that we can possibly bestow on them? "I should be sure,"
you say, "that the sun and the moon really wish to do us a service
if it was possible for them to be unwilling; but they cannot help
being in motion. In short, let them halt and discontinue their
work." But see in how many ways this argument may be refuted.
It is not true that a man who is unable to refuse is for that reason
the less willing to do; nay, the greatest proof of a fixed desire is
the impossibility of its being altered. {duty+} A good
man is unable to fail to do what he does; for unless he did it, he
would not be a good man. And, therefore, a good man gives a
benefit, not because he does what he ought to do, but because,it is
not possible for him not to do what he ought to do. Besides,
it makes a great difference whether you say: "It is not
possible for him not to do this," because he is forced to do it, or
"It is not possible for him to be unwilling." For, if he is
compelled to do it, I owe my benefit, not to him, but to the one who
forces him; if he is compelled to wish to do it for the reason that
he finds nothing better that he wishes to do, it is a case of the
man forcing himself; so, while, in the one case, I should not be
indebted to him on the ground that he was forced, in the other, I am
indebted to him on the ground that he forces himself. "Let them cease
wishing,"/a you say. At this point the following question
should occur to you. Who is so crazy as to deny that an
impulse that is in no danger of ceasing and being changed into the
exact opposite can be a desire, when, on the contrary, no one must
appear more surely to have desire than one whose desire is so
completely fixed as to be <Ess3-405>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxi. 4-xxiii. 1
everlasting?/a Or, if even he who is able at
any moment to change his desire may be said to have desire, shall
not he whose nature does not admit his changing a desire appear to
have desire? "Very
well! let them stop moving if they can," you say. But you
really mean this: {Ode_to_Duty+}
"Let all the heavenly 'bodies, separated as they are by vast
distances and appointed to the task of guarding the universe, leave
their posts; let sudden confusion arise, let stars clash with stars,
let the harmony of the world be destroyed, and the divine creations
totter to destruction; let the heavenly mechanism, movin as it does
with the swiftest speed, abandon in the midst of its course the
progressions that had been promised for so many ages, and let the
heavenly bodies that now, as they alternately advance and retreat,
by a timely balancing keep the world at an equable temperature be
suddenly consumed by flames, and, with their infinite variations
broken up, let them all pass into one condition; let fire claim all
things, then let sluggish darkness take its place, and let these
many gods/b be swallowed up in the bottomless abyss." Is it worth
while to cause all this destruction in order to convince you? They
do you a service even against your will, and for your sake they
follow their courses even if these result from some earlier and more
important cause.
Remark, too, at this point, that the gods are constrained by no
external force, but that their own will is a law to them for all
time. {duty+} What they have determined upon,
they do not change, and, consequently, it is impossible that they
should appear likely to do something although it is against their
will, since they have willed to <Ess3-407>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxiii. 1-5
persist in doing whatever it is impossible
for them to cease from doing,/a and the gods never repent of their
original decision. Undoubtedly, it is not in their power to
halt and to desert to an opposite position, but it is for no other
reason than that their own resolution holds them to their purpose;
and they continue in it, not from weakness, but because they have no
desire to stray from the best course, and it was decreed that this
is the path for them to follow. Moreover, when, at the time of
the original creation, they set in order the universe, they had
regard also for our interests, and took account of man; it cannot be
thought, therefore, that they follow their courses and display their
work merely for their own sake, for we also are a part of that
work. We are indebted, therefore, to the sun and the moon and
the rest of the heavenly host for a benefit, because, even though
the purposes for which they rise are in their eyes more important,
nevertheless in their progress toward these greater things they do
assist us. Besides, too, they assist us in accordance with a
set purpose, and, therefore, we are placed under obligation to them,
because we do not stumble upon a benefit from those who are unaware
of their gift, but they knew that we should receive the gifts that
we do; and, although they may have a greater purpose, and greater
reward for their effort than the mere preservation of mortal
creatures, yet from the beginning of things their thought has been
directed also to our interests, and from the order bestowed upon,
the world it becomes clear that they did not regard their interest
in us as a matter of very small concern. We owe filial duty to
our parents, and yet many at the time of their union had no thought
of <Ess3-409>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxiii. 5-8
begetting us. But it is not possible
for us to suppose that the gods did not know what they would
accomplish when they promptly supplied to all men food and support,
nor were those for whom they produced so many blessings begotten
without purpose.
Nature took thought of us before she created us, nor are we such a
trifling creation that we could merely have dropped from her
hand. {Nature+} See how great privilege
she has bestowed upon us, how the terms of man's empire do not
restrict him to mankind; see how widely she allows our bodies to
roam, she has not confined them within the limits of the land, but
has dispatched them into every part of her domain; see how great is
the audacity of our minds, how they alone either know, or seek, the
gods, and, by directing their thought on high, commune with powers
divine. You will discover that man is not a hasty and
purposeless creation. Among the greatest of her works Nature
has none of which she can more boast, or, surely, no other to which
she can boast. What madness it is to quarrel with the gods
over their gift! How shall a man show gratitude to those to
whom he cannot return gratitude without expenditure, if he denies
that he has received anything from beings from whom he has received
most of all, from those who are always ready to give and will never
expect return? And how blind men are not to feel indebted to
someone for the very reason that he is generous even to one who
denies his gift, and to call the very continuance and succession of
his benefits a proof that he is forced to give, them! Put in
the lips of these such words as: "I don't want it!", "Let him
keep it!", "Who asks him for it?" and all the other utterances of
insolent minds. Yet it is not true that you are under less <Ess3-411>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxiii. 8-xxv. 2
obligation to one whose bounty extends to
you even while you deny it, whose benefits include even this the
greatest of all - a readiness to give to you even while you
complain. Do you
not see how parents force their children in the stage of tender
infancy to submit to wholesome measures? Though the infants
struggle and cry, they tend their bodies with loving care, and,
fearing that their limbs may become crooked from too early liberty,
they swathe them in order that they may grow to be straight, and
later they force them to take a liberal education, and, if they are
unwilling, resort to the incentive of fear; finally, upon the
recklessness of youth they inculcate thrift, decency, and good
habits and use force if it is too unheedful. As they grow up,
too, and are now their own masters, if from fear or from
insubordination they refuse needed remedies, sternness and force are
applied. And so the greatest of all benefits are those that,
while we are either unaware or unwilling, we receive from our
parents. Like those who are ungrateful and repudiate benefits, not
because they do not wish them, but in order to escape obligation,
are those who at the other extreme are too grateful, who pray that
some trouble or some misfortune may befall those who have placed
them under obligation, in order that they may have a chance to prove
how gratefully they remember the benefit they have received.
It is debated whether they are right in doing this, and act from a
dutiful desire. They are very much in the same state of mind
as those who are inflamed with abnormal love, who long for their
mistress to be exiled in order that they may accompany her in her
loneliness and <Ess3-413>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxv. 2-xxvi. 1
flight, who long that she may be poor in
order that she may have more need of their gifts, who long that she
may be ill in order that they may sit at her bedside, who, though
her lovers, pray for all that an enemy might long for her to
have. And so the results of hatred and insane love are almost
the same. Somewhat similar is the case of those who long for
their friends to have troubles in order that they may remove them,
and arrive at beneficence by doing an injury, though it would be
better for them to do nothing than by a crime to seek an opportunity
for doing a duty. What should we think if a pilot should pray to the
gods for fierce tempests and storms in order that danger might cause
more esteem for his skill? What, if a general should beg that a vast
force of the enemy might surround his camp, fill the trenches by a
sudden charge, tear down the rampart around his panic-stricken army,
and plant its hostile standards in the very gates - all in order
that he might have greater glory in coming to the rescue of his
drooping and shattered fortunes? All those who ask the gods to
injure those whom they themselves intend to help use odious means to
bring them benefits, and wish them to be laid low before they raise
them up. To desire to injure one whom you cannot in all honour
fail to help is a sense of gratitude cruelly distorted. "My prayer," you say,
"does him no harm, because at the same time that I wish for his
danger I wish for his relief." What you mean is, not that you do no
wrong, but that you do less than if you were to wish for his danger
without wishing for his relief. But it is wicked to submerge a
man in water in order that you may pull him out, to throw him down
in order <Ess3-415>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxvi. 1-xxvii. 2
that you may raise him up, to imprison him
in order that you may release him. To end an injury is not a
benefit, and there is never any merit in removing a burden which the
one who removes it had himself imposed. I would rather have
you not wound me than cure my wound. You may gain my
gratitude, not by wounding me in order that you may have a chance to
cure me, but by curing me because I have been wounded. There
is never any pleasure in a scar except in comparison with a wound,
for, while we are glad that this has healed, we would rather not
have had it. If you wished this to be the fortune of one from
whom you received a benefit, your desire would be cruel; how much
more cruel to wish it for one to whom you are indebted for a
benefit! "I pray
at the same time," you say,"that I may bring him aid." In the first
place - to stop you in the middle of your prayer - you at once show
yourself ungrateful; what you wish to bestow upon him I have not yet
heard, what you wish him to suffer I now know. You pray that anxiety
and fear and even some greater evil may befall him. You hope that he
may need help - this is to his disadvantage. You hope that he
may need help from you - this is for your advantage. You wish,
not to aid him, but to pay him; but one who shows such eagerness
wishes, not to pay, but to be freed from debt. So the only
part of your prayer that might have seemed to be honourable is
itself the base and ungrateful feeling of unwillingness to remain
under obligation; for you hope, not that vou may have an opportunity
of returning gratitude, but that he may be under the necessity of
imploring your help. You make yourself the superior, and force
one who has done you a service to <Ess3-417>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxvii. 2-6
grovel at your feet, which is wrong.
How much better would it be to remain indebted with an honourable
intention than to be released by evil means! You would be less
guilty if you were to repudiate what you had received; for his only
loss would be what he had given. But as it is, you wish him to
become subservient to you, by loss of his property and change of
social position to be reduced to the state of being in a worse
plight than his own benefits relieved. Shall I count you
grateful? Make your prayer in the hearing of the man whom you
wish to help! Do you call that a prayer, in which a grateful
friend and an enemy might equally share, and which, if the last part
were unuttered, you would not doubt that an adversary and foe had
made? Even the enemy will sometimes hope to capture certain
cities in order to spare them, and to conquer certain men in order
to pardon them, yet these will not for that reason fail to be
hostile desires, in which a very great kindness is preceded by
cruelty. Finally, what sort of prayers do you suppose those
can be which no one will desire so little to see fulfilled as he in
whose behalf they are made? You treat a man very badly in
wishing him to be injured by the gods, and you treat the gods
themselves unfairly in wishing him to be rescued by yourself; for
you assign a most cruel role to them, and a kindly one to
yourself. The gods must do him an injury in order that you may
do him a service. If you suborned someone to be his accuser,
and then withdrew him, if you entangled him in a lawsuit, and then
suddenly quashed it, no one would be in doubt about your
baseness. What difference does it make whether you <Ess3-419>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxvii. 6-xxix. 1
try. to accomplish your purpose by
chicancry. or by prayer, except that by prayer you summon against
him adversaries that are more powerful? You have no right to
say: "What harm, pray, do I do him?" Your prayer is either
futile or harmful, nay, harmful even if it is in vain. God is
responsible for all that you fail to accomplish, but all that you
pray for is injury. Wishing is enough we ought to be just as angry
with you as if your wish were fulfilled. "If my prayers," you
say, "had had any power, they would also have had power to bring you
safety." In the first place, you desire for me certain danger that
is subject to uncertain succour. Again, suppose you consider
both certain, the injury comes first. Besides, while you know
the terns of your prayer, I have been caught in a storm, and am
doubtful of gaining the protection of a harbour. Do you think
what torture it was to have needed help even if I received it?
To have been panic- stricken even if I was saved? To have
pleaded my cause even if I was acquitted? No matter how welcome the
end of any fear may be, firm and unshaken security is even more
welcome. Pray that it may be in your power to repay my benefit
when I shall need it, not that I may need it. If it were in
your power, you would yourself have done what you pray for.
How much more righteous would have been this prayer! "I pray
that he may be in a position always to dispense benefits, and never
to need them; that he may be attended by the means which he uses so
generously in giving bounty and help to others; that he may never
have lack of benefits to bestow {Timon+} <Ess3-421>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxix. 1-xxx. 2
nor regret for those bestowed; may his
nature that of itself is inclined to pity, kindness, and mercy find
stimulus and encouragement from a host of grateful persons, and may
he be fortunate enough to find them without the necessity of testing
them; may none find him implacable, and may he have need to placate
none; may Fortune continue to bestow on him such unbroken favour
that it will be impossible for anyone to show gratitude to him
except by feeling it." How much more proper are such prayers as
these, which do not make you wait for an opportunity, but show your
gratitude at once! For what is there to prevent your returning
gratitude to a benefactor while his affairs are prosperous?
How many ways there are by which we may repay whatever we owe even
to the well-to-do! - loyal advice, {Kent+}
constant intercourse, polite conversation {Castiglione+}
that pleases without flattery+, attentive ears if he should
wish to ask counsel, safe ears if he should wish to be confidential,
and friendly intimacy. Good fortune has set no one so high
that he does not the more feel the want of a friend because he wants
for nothing. This waiting for an opportunity is sorry business
- the thought is to be banished and utterly rejected from every
prayer. Must the gods show their anger before you can show
gratitude? Do you not understand that you are doing wrong from
the very fact that they treat better the one to whom you are
ungrateful? Set before your mind the dungeon, chains,
disgrace, slavery, war, poverty -these are the opportunities for
which you pray. If anyone has had dealings with you, it is
through these that he gets his <Ess3-423>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxx. 2-6
discharge! Why do you not wish,
instead, that the man to whom you owe most may be powerful and
happy? For, as I have said, what prevents your returning
gratitude even to those who are endowed with the utmost good
fortune? The opportunities for doing this, you will find, are
ample and varied. What! do you not know that one can pay a
debt even to a rich man? Nor shall I censure vou if you are
unwilling. Yet, granted that a man's wealth and success may
shut you off from all gifts, I will show you what the highest in the
land stand in need of, what the man who possesses everything lacks -
someone, assuredly who will tell him the truth, who will deliver
from the constant cant and falsehood that so bewilder him with lies
that the very habit of listening to flatteries instead of facts has
brought him to the point of not knowing what truth really is.
Do you not see how such persons are driven to destruction by the
absence of frankness and the substitution of cringing obsequiousness
for loyalty? No one is sincere in expressing approval or
disapproval, but one person vies with another in flattery, and,
while all the man's friends have only one object, a common aim to
see who can deceive him most charmingly, he himself remains ignorant
of his own powers, and, believing himself to be as great as he hears
he is, he brings on wars that are useless and will imperil the
world, breaks up a useful and necessary peace, and, led on by a
madness that no one checks, sheds the blood of numerous persons,
destined at last to spill his own. While without investigation such
men claim the undetermined as assured, and think that it is as
disgraceful to be diverted from their purpose as to be defeated, and
believe that what has already <Ess3-425>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxx. 6-xxxi. 4
reached its highest development, and is even
then tottering, will last for ever, they cause vast kingdoms to come
crashing down upon themselves and their followers. And, living
in that gorgeous show of unreal and swiftly passing blessings, they
failed to grasp that from the moment when it was impossible for them
to hear a word of truth they ought to have expected nothing but
misfortune. {Lear_whole_plot+} When Xerxes declared
war on Greece, everyone encouraged his puffed-up mind that had
forgotten what slender reasons he had for confidence. One
would say that the Greeks could not even endure the announcement of
war, and would take to flight at the first rumour of his arrival;
another, that there was not the slightest doubt that with that vast
force Greece could be, not only conquered, but crushed; that there
was more need to fear that his army would find the cities abandoned
and empty, and that the headlong flight of the enemy would leave but
a vast wilderness in which his forces would have no chance to
display their strength. Another would say that the world was
scarcely big enough to contain him, that the seas were too narrow
for his fleets, the camps for his soldiers, the plains for the
manoeuvres of his cavalry forces, and that the sky was scarcely wide
enough to allow every man to hurl his darts at once. While
much boasting of this sort was going on around him, exciting the
man, who had already too high opinion of himself, to a frantic
pitch, Demaratus, the Lacedaemonian, alone told him that that very
multitude, on which he congratulated himself, disorganized and
unwieldy as it was, was in itself a danger to its leader, for that
it had, not strength, but <Ess3-427>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxi. 4-9
mere weight; that forces that were too large
could never be controlled, and that an army that could not be
controlled did not last long. "The Lacedaemonians," he said,
"will meet you on the first mountain, and immediately give you a
foretaste of their quality. These countless thousands of
various nations will be held in check by three hundred men"; they
will stand.firmly at their post, they will defend the pass entrusted
to them with their arms, and block the way with their bodies; all
Asia will not drive them from their position; pitifully few as they
are, they will stop all this threatened invasion and the wild onrush
of almost the whole human race. When Nature, changing her
laws, has allowed you to traverse the sea, you will be held up on a
footpath, and will be able to estimate your later losses when you
have reckoned the price the pass of Thermopylae cost you; when you
have learned that you can be checked, you will know that you can be
routed. The Greeks will retreat before you in many places as if
swept away bv some mountain torrent that in the first onrush
descends with great terror; then from this side and that they will
rise against you, and crush you by the might of your own
forces. What is commonly said is true - your preparations for
war are too great to find room in the country that you mean to
attack, but this fact is to our disadvantage. Greece will
conquer you, for the very reason that she has no room for you; you
cannot use the whole of you. Besides, and in this lies your only
hope of victory, you will not be able to rush forward at the first
attack, and bear aid to your men if they yield, or to support and
strengthen their wavering ranks; you will have lost the victory long
before you know that you have <Ess3-429>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxi. 10-xxxii. 1
been conquered. However, you may well
suppose that your army will be able to hold out for the reason that
not even its leader knows its numbers; but there is nothing so large
that it cannot perish, and, though there may be no other agents, its
very size gives birth to the cause of its destruction." It all
happened as Demaratus had predicted. And to him who assailed
the works of man and God, and removed whatever blocked his path,
three hundred men cried, "Halt," and, when everywhere throughout the
whole of Greece the Persian had been laid low, he understood how
great a difference there was betwee <?> n a mob and an
army! And so Xerxes, made more unhappy by his shame than by
his loss, expressed his thanks to Demaratus because he had been the
only one to tell him the truth, and permitted him to ask any reward
he pleased. That he asked was that he should be allowed to
enter Sardis, the largest city of Asia, riding in a chariot and
wearing a tiara erect upon his head, a privilege that was accorded
only to kings. He had earned his reward before he asked for
it, but how pitiable the nation in which the only man who told the
king the truth was one who did not tell it to himself! The deified Augustus
banished his daughter/a who was shameless beyond the indictment of
shamelessness, and made public the scandals of the imperial house -
that she had been accessible to scores of paramours, that in
nocturnal revels she had roamed about the city, that the very forum
and the rostrum, from which her father had proposed a law against
adultery, had been chosen by the daughter for her debaucheries, that
she had daily resorted to the statue of Marsyas,/b and, laying aside
the role of adulteress, <Ess3-431>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxii. 1 - xxxiii. 1
there sold her favours, and sought the right
to every indulgence with even an unknown paramour. Carried away by his
anger, he divulged all these crimes, which, as emperor, he ought to
have punished, and equally to have kept secret, because the foulness
of some deeds recoils upon him who punishes them. Afterwards,
when with the lapse of time shame took the place of anger, he
lamented that he had not veiled with silence matters that he had not
known until it was disgraceful to mention them, and often
exclaimed: "If either Agrippa or Maecenas had lived, none of
this would have happened to me!" So difficult was it for one who had
so many thousands of men to repair the loss of two! When his
legions were slaughtered, others were at once enrolled; when his
fleet was wrecked, within a few days a new one was afloat; when
public buildings were swept away by fire, finer ones than those
destroyed rose in their place. But the place of Agrippa and
Maecenas remained empty all the rest of his life. What!
Am I to suppose that there were no more like them who could take
their place, or that it was the fault of Augustus himself, because
he chose rather to sorrow than to search for others? There is
no reason for us to suppose that Agrippa and Maecenas were in the
habit of speaking the truth to him; they would have been among the
dissemblers if they had lived. It is a characteristic of the
kingly mind to praise what has been lost to the detriment of what is
present, and to credit those with the virtue of telling the truth
from whom there is no longer any danger of hearing it. But, to
return to my subject, you see how easy it is to return gratitude to
the prosperous and those who <Ess3-433>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxiii. 1-xxxiv. 1
have beep placed at the summit of human
power. Tell them, not what they wish to hear, but what they
will wish they had always heard; sometimes let a truthful voice
penetrate ears that are filled with flatteries; give them useful
advice. {Kent+} Do you ask what you can
bestow on a fortunate man? Teach him not to trust his
felicity, let him know that it must be sustained by hands that are
many and faithful. Will you not have conferred enough upon him
if you rob him of the foolish belief that his power will endure for
ever, and teach him that the gifts of chance soon pass, and depart
with greater speed than they come; that the descent from the summit
of fortune is not made by the same stages by which it was reached,
but that often it is only a step from the height of good fortune to
ruin?{Lear+} You do not know how great is the
value of friendship if you do not understand that you will give much
to the man to whom you have given a friend, something rare not only
in great houses, but in the ages, something of which there is
nowhere a greater dearth than where it is supposed most of all to
abound. What! Do you think that those lists, which a
nomenclator a can scarcely hold either in his memory or in his hand,
are the lists of friends? Your friends are not those who, in a
long line, knock at your door, whom you distribute into the two
classes of those to be admitted first, and those to be second! It is an old trick of
kings and those who imitate kings to divide the company of their
friends into classes, and but a part of their arrogance to count
crossing, even touching, their threshold a great privilege, and as
an honour to grant you permission to sit nearer the front door, and
to be the first to set <Ess3-435>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxiv. 1-xxxv. 1
foot inside the house, in which, in turn,,
there are any other doors that will shut out even those who have
gained admittance. With us, Gaius Gracchus and, a little
later, Livius Drusus were the first to set the fashion of
classifying their followers, and of receiving some in privacy, some
in company with others, and others en masse. These men,
consequently, had chief friends, ordinary friends, never true
friends. Do you call a man who must stand in line to receive
your greeting a friend? Or can anyone possibly reveal loyalty
to you who, through doors that are opened grudgingly, does not so
much enter as sneak in? Can anyone reach the point of even
approaching to frankness when he must take his turn simply to say
"How do you do?", the ordinary and common term of greeting
universally used by strangers? And so, whenever you go to wait
upon any of the men whose receptions upset the whole city, even
though you find the streets beset with a huge throng of people, and
the ways jammed with the crowds of those passing in both directions,
yet you may be sure that you are going to a place full of people,
but void of friends. We must look for a friend, not in a
reception hall, but in the heart; there must he be admitted, there
retained, and enshrined in affection. Teach a man this - and
you show gratitude! You have a poor opinion of yourself if you are
useful to a friend only when he is in distress, if you are
unnecessary when fortune smiles. As you conduct yourself
wisely in doubtful, in adverse, and in happy circumstances by
exercising prudence in case of doubt, bravery in adversity, and
restraint in good fortune, so under all circumstances you can make
yourself useful to a friend. In adversity do <Ess3-437>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxv. 1-4
not abandon him, {Kent+} but do
not wish him misfortune; none the less, without your wishing it, in
the many and varied incidents of human life, many things will befall
him that will provide you with an opportunity of displaying your
lovalty. As he who prays that another may have riches in the
hope that he may get a share of them, has an eye to his own
interests although he offers his prayer ostensibly for the benefit
of the other, so he who prays that a friend may have some dire need
from which he may rescue him by his help and loyalty, which is
really the wish of an ingrate, sets himself before his friend, and
deems it worth while that his friend should be wretched in order
that he may show himself grateful, for this very reason proves
himself ungrateful; for he wishes to get rid of a burden, and to
free himself from a heavy load. It makes a great difference
whether you hasten to return gratitude in order that you may repay a
benefit, or in order that you may not be under obligation. He
who wishes to repay a benefit will adjust himself to the convenience
of his friend, and will hope for the arrival of a suitable
opportunity; he who only wishes to get rid of a burden will be eager
to accomplish this by any means whatever, which is the worst sort of
wish: "This haste," you say, "shows that one is exceedingly
grateful!" I cannot express the matter more clearly than by
repeating what I have said. You wish, not to return, but to
escape from, a benefit. You seem to say: "When shall I
be rid of it? I must strive in every possible way to avoid
being indebted to him." If you wished to pay a debt to him with
money from his own pocket, you would appear to be very far from
being grateful. This which you do desire is even more unjust;
for <Ess3-439>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxv. 4-xxxvii. 1
you invoke curses upon him, and call down
terrible imprecations upon the head of one whom you hold
sacred. No one, I suppose, would have any doubt about the
cruelty of your. intention if you openly invoked upon him poverty,
or captivity, or hunger and fear. But what difference does it
make whether that is an uttered or a silent prayer? For
someone of these things you do desire. But go now and suppose
that it is gratitude to do what not even an ungrateful man would do,
provided he confined himself to repudiation of the benefit, and
stopped short of hatred! Who will say that
Aeneas is righteous if he wished his native city to be captured in
order that he might rescue his father from captivity? Who will
point to the Sicilian youths/a as good models for children if they
had prayed that Aetna, all aglow and afire, might hurl forth a huge
volume of flame with unusual violence in order to give them an
opportunity of showing their devotion their parents by rescuing them
from the midst of the conflagration? Rome owes nothing to
Scipio if he fostered the Carthaginian War in order that he might
end it. She owes nothing to the Decii/b for saving their city by
dying if they prayed beforehand that they might find in some
desperate need of the state an opportunity to show their heroic
devotion. It is a burning disgrace for a physician to try to
make practice. Many who have aggravated and augmented an
illness in order that they may win greater fame by curing it have
not been able to banish it, or have conquered it at the cost of
great suffering on the part of their victims. It is said (at any
rate Hecaton tells this story) that, when Callistratus/c was going
into exile, forced into it <Ess3-441>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxvii. 1-xxxviii, 1
along with many others by his factious and
outrageously lawless country, and heard someone express the hope
that dire necessity might force the Athenians to recall the exiles,
he cried God forbid such a return!" xxx Our countryman Rutilius a
showed even more spirit. When someone tried to console him by
saying that civil war was threatening, and that in a short time all
exiles would be brought back, he replied: "What sin have I
committed that you should wish me a more unhappy return than
departure? I should much prefer to have my country blush for
my exile than weep at my return!" The exile that causes no one less
shame than the victim is not exile at all. But as these men
maintained their duty as good citizens in being unwilling to be
restored to their homes at the cost of a public disaster, because it
was better that two should suffer from undeserved misfortune than
that all should suffer from universal misfortune, so, in like
manner, he does not maintain the character of a grateful man who
wishes that another, who has done him a service, may be loaded with
troubles in order that he himself may remove them, because, even if
his purpose is good, his desire is evil. To put out a fire that you
yourself have caused does not excuse you - still less do you
credit. In some states an unholy prayer was treated as a
crime. At any rate, at Athens Demades/b won a suit against a man who
sold funeral requirements, by proving that he had prayed for great
gain, and that he could not have been successful unless many persons
had died. Yet the question is often raised whether he was
rightly convicted. Perhaps he prayed, not that he might sell
to many, but that he might sell at a <Ess3-443>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxviii. 2-5
good profit - that what he would naturally
sell might be bought cheaply. Since his business consisted in buying
and selling why do you restrict his prayer to one side of the
transaction when there was gain in both? Besides, you might convict
everyone who followed that business; for they all wish, that is,
secretly pray for, the same thing. You will have to convict,
too, a great part of the human race, for who does not derive, gain
from another's distress? The soldier, if he wants glory, prays
for war; the farmer is cheered by the high price of grain; a number
of lawsuits raise the price of eloquence; the doctor makes money
from an unhealthy season; the vender of sybaritic wares is enriched
by the corruption of youth; if no houses should be damaged by storm
or fire, the builder's trade will suffer. One man's prayer was
detected, but, all make a similar prayer. Or do you suppose that
Arruntius and Haterius, and all the rest who have followed the
profession of hunting legacies, do not put up the same prayers that
funeral directors and undertakers make. Yet these do not know
whose death it is that they are praying for, while the former long
for the death of their most intimate friends, from whom on account
of friendship they have most hope of a legacy. No one's living
causes the latter any loss, while the former are worn out if a
victim is slow in dying; they pray, therefore, not only that they
may receive what they have earned by base servitude, but also that
they may be released from the burdensome tribute. There is no doubt,
therefore, that these pray more earnestly for that which convicted
the Athenian, for whoever is likely to profit them by dying injures
them by living. Yet the prayers of all these men, while well
known, <Ess3-445>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xxxviii. 5-xl. 2
are unpunished. Lastly, let every man
examine himself let him retire into the secrecy of his heart, and
discover what it is that he has silently prayed for. How many
prayers there are which he blushes to acknowledge, even to
himself! How few that we could make in the hearing of a
witness! But not
everything that is blameworthy is to be considered also a crime, as,
for instance, this prayer of a friend, which we are considering,
for, while his purpose was good, his method was evil, and he fell
into the very fault he was trying to avoid. For he is
ungrateful while he hurries - to show his gratitude. He prays
aloud: "May he fall into my power, may he need my influence,
may it not be possible for him to find safety, honour, or security
without me, may he be so unhappy that whatever I return to him will
count as a benefit." What the ears of the gods hear is: "May
he be beset by domestic intrigues which I alone shall be able to
crush, may he be assailed by a powerful and bitter enemy, by a
hostile mob supplied with arms, may he be hard pressed by a
creditor, or by an informer." See how just you are! You would
not have prayed for any of these things if he had not given to you a
benefit. To say nothing of your other more serious sin in
returning the worst for the best, you are certainly at fault in not
waiting for the fitting time for each particular action, for it is
as wrong to anticipate this as to fall behind it. As a benefit
ought not always to be accepted, so it ought not in every case to be
returned. If you were to make return to me though I did not
need it, you would be ungrateful; how much more ungrateful you are
if you force me to need it! Wait a while! Why are you
unwilling to allow my gift to linger in <Ess3-447>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xl. 2-xlii. 1
your hands? Why do you resent being
under obligation? Why, as though you were dealing with a sharp
usurer, are you in such a hurry to square and close your
account? Why do you want to make trouble for me? Why do
you turn the gods against me? If this is your way of making
repayment, what would you do if you were exacting repayment? Above all, therefore,
Liberalis, let us learn this - to rest easy under the obligation
from benefits, and to watch for opportunities of returning them, not
to manufacture them. Let us remember that this very eagerness
to set oneself free at the first possible moment marks one as
ungrateful; for a man is not glad to repay a benefit that he is
unwilling to owe, and one that he is not willing to keep he counts,
not a gift, but a burden. How much better and more seemly it
is for a man to keep in view the services of friends, and to offer,
not to obtrude, his own, and not to count himself a mere debtor; for
a benefit is a common bond and binds two persons together.
Say: "I make no delay in returning what is yours; I hope you
will gladly accept it. If a cruel fortune threatens either of
us, and some fate decrees either that you must accept return of your
benefit, or that I must accept a second one, let him give by
preference who is used to giving. I am ready:
'Tis not for Turiius to
delay./a This is the spirit I shall show whenever the
time comes; meanwhile the gods are my witnesses." I have often observed
in you, Liberalis, and, as it were, "laid hand on" a feeling of
nervous fear that you might be remiss in the performance of any
duty. Anxiety ill becomes the grateful heart, which, on <Ess3-449>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xlii. 1-xliii. 2
the contrary; should show the utmost
self-confidence and that all worry has been banished because of the
consciousness of true love. To say "Take back" casts as much
reproach as to say "You owe." Let this be the first rule in giving a
benefit, that the right to choose the time of having it returned is
the giver's. But you say: "I am afraid that men will
talk about me later." If a man is grateful, not because of his
conscience, but because of his reputation, his motive is
wrong. You have in this matter two judges - your benefactor,
whom you ought not to fear, and yourself, whom you cannot
fear. "What, then," you say, "if no opportunity comes?
Shall I always remain in debt?" You will remain in debt, but openly
in debt, gladly in debt - you will view with great pleasure what has
been left in your hands. A man who is irked at not having
returned a benefit is sorry that he received it. Why, if you
thought a man was worthy to make you his debtor, do you think that
he is unworthy of your remaining long in debt? Those who think that
to proffer and to bestow and to fill many men's pockets and houses
with their gifts are proof of a great soul make a great mistake,
since sometimes these are due, not so much to a large soul, as to a
large fortune; {Timon+} they do not know how much
greater and more difficult it is at times to take, than to lavish,
gifts. For, although I would not disparage either act, since
both are of equal value when Virtue directs them, to become indebted
for a benefit requires no smaller spirit than to give it; of the
two, the former, in fact, is the more laborious, as greater effort
is expended in guarding, than in giving, the objects that are
received. Therefore we ought not <Ess3-451>
ON BENEFITS, VI. xliii. 2-3
to be worried over how soon we can repay,
nor should we rush to do so at an unseemly time, for he who hastens
to return gratitude at the wrong time is as much at fault as he who
is remiss in returning it at the proper time. He has placed
his gift in my hands; I have no fear on his account or on my
own. He has good security; he cannot lose his benefit unless
he loses me, nay, not even if he loses me. I have paid him my
thanks - that is, I have made return. He who thinks too much
about returning a benefit must suppose that the other thinks too
much about having it returned. One should lend himself to both
points of view. If a man wishes his benefit to be returned,
let us repay and return it cheerfully; if he prefers that it should
remain in our custody, why do we dig up his treasure? Why do
we refuse to guard it? He deserves to be allowed to do
whichever he pleases, As for rumour and reputation, let us consider
them as matters that must, not guide, but follow, our actions. <Ess3-453>
BOOK VII
BE of good cheer, Liberalis
The land is close - I will not
keep you long By rambling outbursts of a
long-drawn song./a This book gathers up the remnants,
and, after the subject has been exhausted, I am casting about to
discover, not what I shall say, but what I have not said. If
there is anything in it that could be omitted, you will take it in
good part, since it was for your sake that I did not omit it. If I had wished to
curry favour for myself, I ought to have let my work grow gradually
in interest, and to have reserved for the last a part that any
reader would be eager for even if he were surfeited. But all
that is most essential I have massed together at the beginning; now
I am merely recovering whatever escaped me. Nor, seriously, if
you ask me, do I think that, after stating the rules that govern
conduct, there is very much point in my pursuing the other questions
that have been raised, not to further the health of the mind, but to
provide exercise for the intellect. For Demetrius the
Cynic, a great man, in my opinion, even if compared with the
greatest, is fond of stating very admirably that it is far better
for us to possess only a few maxims of philosophy that are <Ess3-455>
ON BENEFITS, VII. 1. 3-7
nevertheless always at our command and in
use, than to acquire vast knowledge, that notwithstanding serves no
practical purpose. "Just as," he says, "the best wrestler is
not one who is thoroughly acquainted with all the postures and grips
of the art, which he will seldom use against an adversary, but he
who has well and carefully trained himself in one or two of them,
and waits eagerly for the opportunity to use them - for it makes no
difference how much he knows if he knows, enough to give him the
victory - , so in this effort of ours there are many points that are
interesting, few that are decisive. Though you may not know
what principle causes the ebb and flow of the ocean tides, why every
seventh year leaves its mark on the life of a man, why the width of
a colonnade, when you look at it from a distance, does not keep its
true proportion, but towards the end grows narrower, and at last the
spaces between the columns disappear, why it is that twins are
conceived separately, but are born together, whether in coition one
act gives birth to two, or each is born from a separate act, why
those who are born together have different destinies, and, though
their births were very close together, are very far apart in the
differences of their experiences it will not do you much harm to
pass over matters which it is neither possible nor advantageous for
you to know. {Prospero+} Truth lurks in deep hiding and
is wrapped in mystery. Nor can we complain that Nature is
grudgingly disposed towards us, for there is nothing that is hard to
discover except that which, when discovered, brings no other reward
than the fact of discovery; all that tends to make us better and
happier has been placed either in plain sight or nearby. The
soul that can scorn all the accidents of fortune, <Ess3-457>
ON BENEFITS, VII. i. 7-ii. 2
that can rise superior to fears, that does
not greedily covet boundless wealth, but has learned to seek its
riches from itself; the soul that can cast out all dread of men and
gods, and knows that it has not much to fear from man and nothing
from God; that, despising all those things which, while they enrich,
harass life, can rise to the height of seeing that death is not the
source of any evil, but the end of many; the soul that can dedicate
itself to Virtue, and think that every path to which she calls, is
smooth; that, social creature that it is and born for the common
good, views the world as the universal home of mankind, that can
bare its conscience to the gods, and, respecting itself more than
all others, always live as if in the sight of men - such a soul,
remote from storms, stands on the solid ground beneath a blue sky,
and has attained to perfect knowledge of what is useful and
essential. All other matters are but the diversions of a
leisure hour; for when the soul has once found this safe retreat, it
may also make excursions into things that bring polish, not
strength, to its powers. {Stoicism_basic+} These are the things
that my friend Demetrius says the tiro in philosophy must grasp with
both hands, these are the precepts that he must never let go, nay,
must cling fast to, and make a part of himself, and by daily
meditation reach the point where these wholesome maxims occur to him
of their own accord, and are promptly at hand whenever they are
desired, and the great distinction between base and honourable
action presents itself without any delay. Let him know that
there is no evil except what is base, and no good except what is
honourable. Let him apply this rule to all the deeds of life;
in accordance with this law let him both order and weigh all his <Ess3-459>
ON BENEFITS, VII. ii. 2-5
actions, and those who are given over to
gluttony and lust, whose minds are deadened by sluggish inaction,
let him judge to be the most wretched of mortals, no matter how
great the splendour of their wealth may be. Let him say to
himself: "Pleasure is frail, shortlived, and prone to pall;
the more eagerly it is indulged, the more swiftly it changes into
the opposite, it forces us straightway either to repentance or to
shame, it has in it nothing of nobility, nothing worthy of the
nature of man, second as he is to the gods, a lowly thing, produced
by subservience to the parts of our body that are either base or
vile, and in the end repulsive.{Lear_disgust+}
True pleasure, worthy either of man or hero, comes, not from filling
and gorging the body and from exciting the lusts that are safest
when they are quiet, but from freedom from all mental disturbance,
both that which is aroused by the ambition of men struggling with
one another, and that which comes, insufferably, from on high when
we give credence to the stories of the gods, and estimate them by
the standard of our own vices." This is the pleasure, constant,
serene, always uncloyed, that is experienced by the man we were just
now delineating, one skilled, so to speak, in the laws of gods and
men. Such a man rejoices in the present, and puts no faith in
the future; for he who leans upon uncertainties can have no sure
support. Free, therefore, from the great anxieties that rack the
mind, there is nothing which he hopes for or covets, and, content
with what he has, he does not plunge into what is doubtful. {Foresight+} And do not suppose
that he is content with a little - all things are his, and not in
the sense in which they were Alexander's, who, although he stood
upon the shore of the Indian Ocean, had need of more territory <Ess3-461>
ON BENEFITS, VII. ii. iii. 2
than that he had passed through. Nor
did he own even the kingdoms that he was holding or had conquered,
while Onesicritus,/a who had been sent ahead to discover new ones,
was wandering about the ocean and stirring up war on unknown
seas. Was it not quite clear that it was a man in need who
pushed his arms beyond the bounds of Nature, who, driven on by
reckless greed, plunged headlong into an unexplored and boundless
sea? What difference does it make how many kingdoms he seized,
how many he bestowed, how many lands submitted to tribute? He
still had need of as much as he still coveted. Nor was this the vice
of Alexander alone, whose successful audacity led him to follow in
the footsteps of Liber and Hercules, but of all those whom Fortune
has goaded on by rich gifts. Consider Cyrus and Cambyses/b and
all the royal line of Persia. Will you find any among them who
was satisfied with the bounds of his empire, who did not end his
life in some plan of advancing farther? Nor need we wonder;
for whatever is gained by covetousness is simply swallowed up and
buried, nor does it make any difference how much you pour into a
vessel that can never be filled. It is only the wise
man who has all things, and has no difficulty in retaining
them. He has no need to send legates across the seas, nor to
measure out camps on hostile shores, nor to place garrisons in
strategic forts - he has no need of a legion or squadrons of
cavalry. Like the immortal gods who govern their realm without
recourse to arms, and still from their serene and lofty heights
safeguard their own, so the wise man performs his duties, however
far <Ess3-463>
ON BENEFITS, VII. iii. 2-iv. 2
reaching they may be, without any turmoil,
and, being the most powerful and best of mankind, sees the whole
human race beneath him. Smile though you may, yet if you
survey the East and the West with your thought, which can penetrate
even to lands that are far removed and shut off by vast wastes, if
you behold all creatures of earth, all the bounteous store, which
Nature so richly pours forth, it is the claim of no mean spirit to
be able to utter these words of God: "All these things are
mine!"{Wdswth+} {Satan+} Thus
it comes that he covets nothing because there is nothing outside of
the all. "This,"
you say, "is the very thing I wanted; I have caught you! I
want to see how you will release yourself from this trap into which
you have fallen of your own accord. Tell me this. If the
wise man possesses everything, how can anyone possibly give anything
to a wise man? For even what one gives to him is already
his. It is impossible, therefore, to bestow a benefit on a
wise man, for whatever is given to him is given out of his own
store; yet you Stoics say that it is possible to give to a wise
man. Know, too, that I raise the same question also with
reference to friends. You say that they have all things in
common; {Friend+ no one, consequently can give
anything to a friend; for he gives to him what is common property.
There is nothing
to prevent a thing's belonging both to the wise man and to him who
actually possesses it as something that was granted and assigned to
him. According to civil law everything belongs to the king,
and yet property, to which the king lays claim by his universal
right, is parcelled out to individual owners, and each separate
thing is someone's <Ess3-465>
ON BENEFITS, VII. iv. 2-6
personal possession. And so we are
able to give to a king a house, or a slave, or money, and are not
said to be bestowing upon him a gift of his own property; for the
right of ownership of all things belongs to the king, the actual
ownership to the individual citizen, We speak of the
territories of the Athenians and the Campanians, which, in turn, the
dwellers divide among themselves by private agreements; and while
the whole land is undoubtedly the property of any commonwealth, each
part of it in turn is reckoned as the possession of its owner; and
we are able, therefore, to present our lands to the state, although
they are said to belong to the state, because, in one way, they are
the state's, in another, mine. Can there be any doubt that a
slave, along with his private savings, belongs to his master?
Yet he can give a present to his master. For it is not true
that a slave owns nothing for the mere reason that he will not be
able to own it if his master should be unwilling for him to own it,
nor is it true that he does not give a present, when he gives it
willingly, for the mere reason that it could have been seized from
him even if he had been unwilling, How can we prove
everything? For we are now both agreed that the wise man
possesses all things; the question that we must settle is how there
can remain any means of showing generosity to one to whom we have
granted all things belong. All things that are in the hands of his
children belong to the father; yet who does not know that even a son
can make a gift to his father? All things belong to the gods;
yet we both offer gifts to the gods, and throw them alms./a It is
not necessarily true that what I <Ess3-467>
ON BENEFITS, VII. iv. 6-v. 2
have is not mine if what is mine is also
yours; for it is possible that the same thing may be both mine and
yours. "He to whom
courtesans belong," you say, "is a pimp; but all things belong to a
wise man, and all things must also include courtesans; therefore
courtesans belong to a wise man. But he to whom courtesans
belong is a pimp; therefore a wise man is a pimp." In the same way
they forbid him to buy anything, for they say: "No one buys
his own property; but all things belong to the wise man; therefore
the wise man buys nothing." In the same way they forbid him to take
a loan, because no one is going to pay interest for the use of his
own money. They raise endless quibbles, although they
perfectly well understand what we mean. For I mean that, while
all things belong to the wise man, each person, nevertheless, has
the ownership of his own property, just as under the best sort of
king everything belongs to the king by his right of authority, and
to his subjects by their individual rights of ownership. The
time will come for proving this statement; meanwhile the question in
hand will be sufficiently answered if I say that it is possible for
me to give to the wise man something that, in one way, belongs to
the wise man, and, in another way, belongs to me. Nor is it
surprising that it is possible to give something to one who
possesses all there is. Suppose I have rented a house from
you; you still have some "right" in it, and I have some right - the
property is yours, the use of the property is mine. Nor,
likewise, will you touch crops, although, they may be growing on
your own <Ess3-469>
ON BENEFITS, VII. v. 2-vi. 3
estate, if your tenant objects; and if the
price of corn becomes too dear, or you are starving, you will
Alas! in vain another's mighty
store behold,/a grown upon your own land, lying upon
your own land, and about to be stored in your own granary.
Nor, although you are the owner, will you set foot on what I have
rented, nor will you take away a slave of yours, now a hireling of
mine; and if I have hired a carriage from you, you will be receiving
a benefit if I permit you to sit in your own vehicle. You see,
therefore, that it becomes possible for someone to receive a present
by receiving what is his own. In all these cases that I have
just cited there are two owners of one and the same thing. How
is it possible? Because one is the owner of the thing, the
other of the use of the thing. We say that certain books are
Cicero's; Dorus, the bookseller, calls these same books his own, and
both statements are true. The one claims them, because he
wrote them, the other because he bought them; and it is correct to
say that they belong to both, for they do belong to both, but not in
the same way. So it is possible for Titus Livius to receive
his own books as a present, or to buy them from Dorus.
Although all things belong to a wise man, yet I am able to give to
him what is individually mine; for, although he is conscious of
possessing all things in the manner of a king, yet the ownership of
the several things is divided among individuals, and it is possible
for him to receive a present and to be indebted and to buy and to
hire. Everything belongs to Caesar, yet the only private and
personal property he has is the <Ess3-471>
ON BENEFITS, VII. vi. 3-vii. 3
imperial treasury; all things are his by
right of his authority, but his personal property is acquired by
right of inheritance. The question may be raised as to what is
his, and what is not his, without assailing his authority; for even
that which the court may decide belongs to another, from another
point view belongs to him. So in his mind the wise man
possesses all things, by actual right and ownership only his own
things. Bion/a at
one time proves by argument that all men are sacrilegious, at
another, that no one is. When he is disposed to hurl all men
from the Tarpeian Rock, he says: "Whoever abstracts and
consumes and appropriates to his own use what belongs to the gods,
commits sacrilege; but all things belong to the gods; that which
anyone abstracts, therefore, he abstracts from the gods, to whom all
things belong; consequently, whoever abstracts anything commits
sacrilege." Again, when he bids men to break into temples and to
pillage the Capitol without fear of punishment, he says that no one
commits sacrilege, because whatever is abstracted from one place
that belongs to the gods is transferred to another place that
belongs to the gods. The answer to this is
that, while it is true that all things belong to the gods, all
things are not consecrated to the gods, and that only in the case of
the things that religion has assigned to a divinity is it possible
to discover sacrilege. That thus, also, the whole world is the
temple of the gods, and, indeed, the only one worthy of their
majesty and grandeur, and yet that there is a distinction between
things sacred and profane; that not all things which it is
<Ess3-473>
ON BENEFITS, VII. vii. 3-viii. 1
lawful to do under the open sky and in the
sight of the stars are lawful to do in the nook to which has been
assigned the name of a sanctuary. The sacrilegious man is not
able, indeed, to do any injury to God, whose own divinity has placed
him beyond the reach of harm, yet he is punished because he aimed an
injury at God - he is subjected to punishment by our feeling and his
own. As, therefore, he who carries off something sacred seems
to have cornmitted a sacrilege, even if the place to which he has
transferred what he had stolen is within the limits of the world, so
it is possible for a theft to be committed upon even a wise man, for
he will be robbed of something, taken, not from that universe which
he possesses, but from the things of which he is the registered
owner, and which are at his individual service. He will claim
his ownership of the former, ownership of the latter he will be
unwilling to have even if he is able, and will give voice to the
famous words that a Roman general uttered when, as a reward for his
prowess and his good service to the state, he was being awarded as
much land as he could have covered in one day's ploughing; "You have
no need," said he, "of a citizen who needs to have more than is
necessary for one citizen." How much more a hero will you think him
for having rejected this gift than for having deserved it! For
many have removed the boundary lines of other men's lands, no one
has set limits to his own! When, therefore, we behold the mind
of the wise man, master as it is of all things and a ranger of the
universe, we say that all things belong to him, although, according
to our every-day law, his only assessment, it may be, will be a
head-tax. It makes <Ess3-475>
ON BENEFITS, VII. viii. 2-ix. 2
a great difference whether his holdings are
estimated by the censor's register, or by the greatness of his
mind. He will pray to be delivered from the ownership of all
the things of which you speak. I shall not remind you
of Socrates, of Chrysippus, of Zeno, and the others, truly great men
- in fact, too great, because envy sets no bounds to our praise of
the ancients. But a little while ago I reminded you of
Demetrius, whom, it seems to me, Nature produced in these times of
ours in order to prove that he could not be corrupted even by us,
and that we could not be reproved even by him - a man of consummate
wisdom, though he himself disclaimed it, of steadfast firmness in
all his purposes, of an eloquence fitted to deal with the mightiest
subjects, not given to graces, nor finical about words, but
proceeding to its theme with great spirit, as impulse inspired
it. {PlainDealer+} I doubt not that this man
was endowed by divine providence with such a life, with such power
of speech in order that our age might not lack either a model or a
reproach. If some god should wish to commit all our wealth to the
hands of Demetrius on the fixed condition that he should not be
allowed to give it away, I am ready to assert that he would refuse
it, and say: "Really, I cannot be bound down by this
inextricable burden, nor, unhampered as I now am, do I mean to be
dragged down to the dregs of existence. Why do you offer to me
what is the bane of all peoples? I would not accept it even if
I intended to give it away, for I see many things that are not fit
for me to bestow. I wish to set clearly before myself the
things that blind the eyes of nations and kings, I wish to behold
the recompenses for your life-blood and your lives. Array
before me first the trophies of <Ess3-477>
ON BENEFITS, VII. ix. 2-x. 1
Luxury, spreading them out in a row, if you
wish, or, as is better, piling them into one heap. I see there
the shell of the tortoise, a most ugly and sluggish creature, bought
for huge sums and embellished with elaborate markings, and the very
variety of their colours, which is their chief attraction, is
accentuated by the application of dyes that resemble the natural
tint. I see there tables of wood, valued at the price of a
senatorial fortune,/a and the more knotted the contortions of the
unhappy tree, the more precious/b it is. I see there objects
of crystal, whose very fragility enhances their price; for to the
ignorant mind, the pleasure of all things is increased by the very
risk that ought to drive pleasure away. I see there murrine
cups/c - men, forsooth, would pay too little for their luxury
unless, when they toasted each other, they had precious stones to
hold the wine they will vomit up! I see pearls - not single
ones designed for each ear, but clusters of them, for the ears have
now been trained to carry their load; they are joined together in
pairs, and above each pair still others are fastened; feminine folly
could not sufficiently have overwhelmed men unless two or three
fortunes had hung in each ear! I see there raiments of silk -
if that can be called raiment, which provides nothing that could
possibly afford protection for the body, or indeed modesty, so that,
when a woman wears it, she can scarcely, with a clear conscience,
swear that she is not naked. These are imported at vast
expense from nations unknown even to trade, in order that our
married women may not be able to show more of their persons, even to
their paramours, in a bedroom than they do on the street. And
how, O Avarice, dost thou fare? How many <Ess3-479>
ON BENEFITS, VII. x. 1-5
are the things that in costliness have
surpassed thy gold! All those that I have mentioned are more
honoured and valued. Now I wish to review thy wealth, the
plates of gold and silver, for which our greed gropes in
darkness. Yet in very truth, the earth, which has revealed
everything that was likely to be of use to us, has hidden these
things, and buried them deep, and weighted them down with all her
mass, regarding them as harmful substances, destined to be a curse
to the nations if brought forth into the light. I see that
iron has been brought forth from the same dark depths that yielded
gold and silver in order that we might not lack either the
instrument or the reward for slaughtering one another. And yet
the forms of thy wealth, so far, have some actual substance; but
there is another in which the mind and the eye alike can be
deceived. I see there allotments, bonds, and securities - the
empty phantoms of ownership, the secret haunts of Avarice devising
some means by which she may deceive the mind that delights in empty
fancies. For what are these things, what are interest and the
account-book and usury, but the names devised for unnatural forms of
human greed? {Shylock+} "I might make
complaint against Nature because she did not hide gold and silver
more deeply, because she did not lay a weight upon them too heavy to
be removed - but these bills of thine, what are they? what the
computations and the sale of time and the blood-thirsty twelve per
cent? Evils that we will, that originate from our own
character, that have in them nothing which can be put before the
eyes, nothing that can be held in the hand - the mere dreams of
empty Avarice! Wretched, indeed, is he <Ess3-481>
ON BENEFITS, VII. x. 5-xii. 1
who can take delight in the huge record of
his estate, in his vast tracts of land that need to be tilled by men
in chains, in huge herds and flocks that need whole provinces and
kingdoms to provide them with pasture, and in private palaces that
cover more ground than great cities! When he has carefully
reviewed all his wealth, in what it is invested and on what it is
squandered, and is puffed up with pride, let him compare all that he
has with what he still covets, and he is a poor man! Let me go
- restore me to the riches that are mine. I know the kingdom
of wisdom, a mighty, a secure kingdom - I possess all in the sense
that all things belong to all!" And so, when Gaius Caesar wanted to
give Demetrius two hundred thousand, he laughingly refused it, not
even deeming it a sum the refusal of which was worth boasting
about! Ye gods and goddesses, what a petty mind Gaius showed
in trying either to compliment or to corrupt him! I must here
render testimony to the distinction of the man. I heard him
say a fine thing when be expressed surprise at the madness of Gaius
in supposing that he could have been influenced by such an
amount. "If he meant to tempt me," said he, "he ought to have
tested me by offering me his whole kingdom." xxx It is possible,
consequently, to bestow a gift on a wise man even if all things
belong to the wise man. And, just as truly, there is nothing
to prevent my making a gift to a friend, although we say that
friends have all things in common. For I have all things in
common with my friend, not as I would with a partner, when one share
would belong to me, and another to him, but as children are the
common possession of <Ess3-483>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xii. 1-5
their father and mother, who, if they have
two, do not each claim one, but they each claim two. First of all, I shall
now proceed to show that every man who invites me to enter into
partnership with him, knows well that he possesses nothing in common
with me. And why ? Because this community of
goods {common_property+} can exist between wise
men only, who alone are capable of knowing friendship; the rest are
just as little friends as they are partners. In the second place,
there are many ways of owning things in common. The seats
reserved/a for the knights belong to all the Roman knights - yet of
these the seat that I have occupied becomes my own property, and, if
I surrender it to anyone, I am supposed to have given him something
although I have only surrendered to him what was common
property. Certain things belong to certain persons under
particular conditions. I have a seat among the knights, not to sell,
not to let, not to dwell in, but to use only for the purpose of
viewing the spectacle. Therefore I am not speaking an untruth
when I say that I have a seat in the equestrian rows. But, if
the equestrian rows are full when I enter the theatre, I both have a
right to a seat there, because I have the privilege of sitting
there, and have not a right, because the seat is occupied by those
who have with me a common right to the space. Consider that
the same relation exists between friends. Whatever our friend
possesses is common to us, but it is the property of the one who
holds it; I cannot use the things against his will. "You are
making fun of me," you say; "if what belongs to my friend is mine, I
have a right to sell it." Not so; for you have no right to sell the
equestrians' seats, and yet they belong to you <Ess3-485>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xii. 5-xiv. 3
in common with the other knights. The
fact that you cannot sell something, or consume it, or alter it for
the better or worse is, in itself, no proof that it does not belong
to you; for something that is yours under particular conditions is
nevertheless yours. . . . /a I have received, but at any rate not
less. Not to prolong the discussion, a benefit cannot be more
than a benefit; but the means employed to convey a benefit may be
both greater and more numerous - the things in which, in short,
one's benevolence runs riot, and indulges itself as lovers are wont
to do, for these by their more numerous kisses and closer embraces
do not increase their love, but give it play. This other question,
which now comes up, has been exhausted in the earlier books, and
will, therefore, be touched upon briefly; for the arguments that
have been given for other cases may be transferred to this.
The question is, whether anyone who has done everything in his power
to return a benefit has returned it. "You may be sure," you
say, "that he has not returned it, for he did everything in his
power to return it; it is evident, therefore, that he did not
accomplish his purpose if he failed to find opportunity for its
accomplishment. And a man does not discharge his debt to a
creditor if he searches everywhere for money in order to be able to
discharge it, and yet has not found it." Some efforts are of such a
character that they are bound to achieve their end; in the case of
others, to have tried in every way to achieve an end takes the place
of achievement. If a physician has made every effort to effect
a cure, he has performed his part; the <Ess3-487>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xiv. 3-6
pleader, if he has used all the power of his
eloquence, fulfils his duty even if his client is convicted; praise
for his generalship is bestowed even upon a vanquished commander if
he has performed his duties with prudence, with diligence, and with
bravery. A man has made every effort to return your benefit,
but your good fortune stood in his way; no hardship befell you which
could put his true friendship to the test; he could not give to you
when you were rich, nor sit at your bedside when you were not sick,
nor succour you when you had no misfortune - this man has repaid
gratitude even if you have not received the return of your
benefit. Moreover, he who is always intent upon this, is on
the watch for an opportunity of doing it, and expends upon it much
thought and much anxiety, has taken more trouble than one who has
had the good fortune to repay his gratitude quickly. Quite
different is the case of the debtor, for it is not enough for him to
have sought for the money unless he pays it; for in his case a harsh
creditor stands over him, who suffers not a single day to pass
without charging him interest; in your case there is a very generous
friend, who, if he saw you rushing about and troubled and anxious,
would say: "This
trouble from thy breast expel/a; cease to cause yourself
concern. I have all that I want from you; you do me an
injustice if you suppose that I desire from you anything further;
your intention has reached me most fully." "Tell me," you
say: "if he had returned the benefit, you would say that he
has shown gratitude; are both, therefore, in the same position - the
one who did not retyrn it?" <Rss3-489>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xiv. 6-xv. 2
On the
other hand, consider this. If he had forgotten the benefit he had
received, if he had not even tried to be grateful, you would say
that he had not shown gratitude. Yet this other man has worn
himself out night and day, and, neglecting all his other duties, has
concentrated on this single one, and has taken pains not to let any
opportunity escape him. Will, therefore, he who has put aside
all concern about showing gratitude and he who has never ceased to
be concerned be considered in the same class? You are unjust
if you require me to pay in fact when you see that I have not failed
in intention. In short, suppose, when you had been taken
captive, that I, having borrowed money, and having made over my
property to my creditor as security, set sail along shores infested
with pirates in the midst of winter with all its fierceness, and
traversed all the perils that even a peaceful sea can offer; that,
having wandered, through all wildernesses, in search of men from
whom every one else was fleeing, I at last reached the pirates, and
found that someone else had ransomed you - will you say that I have
not repaid gratitude? Even if, during that voyage, I was
shipwrecked, and lost the money that I had raised to rescue you,
even if I myself have fallen into the chains which I hoped to remove
from you, will you say that I have not repaid gratitude? No, by the
gods! - the Athenians call Harmodius and Aristogiton/a
"tyrannicides," and the hand that Mucius/b left on the enemy's altar
was as glorious as if it had killed Porsina, and the valour that
struggles against fortune always wins lustre even if it fails to
accomplish the task set before <Ess3-491>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xv. 2-xvi. 2
it. He who pursues opportunities that
elude him, and clutches at them one after another in order that he
may be able to have the means of showing his gratitude, renders far
more than he who without strenuous effort proves himself grateful at
the first opportunity. " But," you say, "your
benefactor bestowed on you two things, his property and his
goodwill; you, likewise, owe him two." You might say this very
properly to one who returns to you goodwill without further effort,
but you cannot say it to one who both wishes and makes effort, and
leaves nothing untried; for, so far as it is in his power, he
bestows on you both. Again, it is not always desirable to pit
number against number; sometimes one thing has the value of two; and
so such ardent and eager desire to repay takes the place of
repayment. And, if the intention without a material offering
has no value in repaying gratitude, no one shows himself grateful to
the gods, to whom the only contribution that we make is
goodwill. "We cannot," you say, " bestow anything else on the
gods." But, if I am also unable to bestow anything else on a man to
whom I ought to return gratitude, why is it that the only means that
I have of showing my gratitude to the gods does not permit me to
show myself grateful to a man? If, however, you ask
me what I think, and wish me to set my seal on the reply, I should
say that the one should consider that he has received the return of
his benefit, while the other should know that he has not returned
it; the one should release the other, while the other should feel
himself bound; the one should say, "I have received," the other, "I
still owe." In the case of every question, let us keep before us the
<Ess3-493>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xvi. 2-5
public good; the door must be closed to all
excuses, to keep the ungrateful from taking refuge in them and using
them to cover their repudiation of the debt. "I have done all
in my power," says he. Well, keep on doing so. Tell me, do you
suppose that our forefathers were so foolish as not to understand
that it was most unjust to consider a man who wasted in debauchery
or gambling the money he had received from a creditor to be in the
same class with one who lost the borrowed property along with his
own in a fire, or by robbery, or some other major mishap? Yet
they accepted no excuses in order to teach men that a promise must
be kept at all costs; in their eyes it was better that a few should
not find even a good excuse accepted than that all should resort to
excuse. You have done everything in order to make return; this
should be enough for your benefactor, it should not be enough for
you. For, just as he is unworthy of being repaid with
gratitude if he permits all your earnest and diligent effort to pass
as nothing, so, if anyone accepts your goodwill as full payment, you
are ungrateful if you are not all the more eager to acknowledge your
indebtedness because he has released you. Do not snatch up
your releaser nor demand witnesses; no whit the less should you seek
opportunities for making full return. Return to one because he
demands repayment, to another because he releases you from the debt;
to the former, because he is bad, to the latter, because he is good.
There is,
consequently, no reason why you should suppose that you have any
concern with the question of whether a man ought to return the
benefit that he has received from a wise man if he has ceased to <Ess3-495>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xvi. xviii. 1
be wise and has turned into a bad man.
For you would return a deposit that you had received from a wise man
even if he had become bad, you would return a loan. What
reason is there why you should not return a benefit also?
Because he has changed, should he change you? Tell me, if you
had received anything from a man when he was well, would you not
return it to him if he were sick, seeing that a friend's weakness
always increases our obligation to him? This other also is
sick - but in his mind; we should help him, and bear with him.
The mind's illness is folly. In order that the
matter may become more intelligible, I think that here I ought to
make a distinction. Benefits are of two kinds - one, the
perfect and true benefit, which only a wise man can give to none but
a wise man; the other, the everyday, common sort, in which we
ignorant men have dealings with each other. With regard to the
latter, there is no doubt that I ought to make return to the giver,
no matter what sort of a man he may be, whether he has turned out to
be a murderer or a thief or an adulterer. Crimes have their
appointed laws; let such men be reformed rather by a judge than by
the ingrate. {judge_not+} Let no man make
you bad because he is. To a good man I shall hand back his
benefit, to a bad one I shall fling it back; to the former, because
I am indebted to him, to the latter, in order that I may no longer
be indebted to him. With regard to the other kind of benefit, a
question arises, for, if I could not have received the benefit
unless I had been a wise man, neither can I return it to the giver
unless he is a wise man. For you say : "Suppose that I
do return it - he is not able to take it <Ess3-497>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xix. 3-6
have returned; I owe protection to a benefit
that has been received, not to one that has been returned.
While it is in my hands, it must be kept safe; but I must give it
back when he demands it even if it escapes from his hands as he
takes it. To a good man I shall make return when it is
convenient; to a bad man, when he asks for it. "You cannot," you say,
"return to him the same sort of benefit that you received; for you
received it from a wise man, you are returning it to a fool." No; I
am returning to him the sort that he is now able to receive, and it
is not my fault if that which I shall return is inferior to what I
received, but the fault lies with him, and if he is restored to
wisdom, I shall return the sort that I received; while he lingers in
evil, I shall return the sort that he is able to receive. "Tell me," you say,
"if he has become, not only bad, but savage, even ferocious, like
Apollodorus or Phalaris, will you return even to such a man a
benefit that you had received?" {Timon+} Nature
does not permit a wise man to suffer so great a change. A man
does not fall from the best state into the worst; even a bad man
must necessarily retain some traces of good; virtue is never so
wholly extinguished as not to leave upon the mind indelible imprints
that no change can ever erase. Wild beasts that have been bred in
captivity, if they escape into the forests, retain something of
their earlier tameness, and are as far removed from the most
peaceful beasts as they are from those that have always been wild
and have never submitted to the hand of man. No one who has
ever adhered to wisdom can fall into the depths of wickedness; its
<Ess3-501>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xix. 6-9
colour is too deeply fixed to be able to
fade altogether from his mind and to take on the hue of evil. In the second place, I
ask you whether the man you are thinking of is ferocious in spirit
only, or whether he bursts forth into acts of public violence?
You have cited the cases of Phalaris and another tyrant, but if,
while an evil man possesses their nature, he keeps it concealed, why
should I not return to him his benefit in order that there may be no
further bond between him and me? If, however, he not only
delights in human blood, but feeds upon it; if also he exercises his
insatiable cruelty in the torture of persons of all ages, and his
frenzy is the result, not of anger, but of a certain delight in
cruelty; if he butchers children before the eyes of their parents;
if, not content with simply killing his victims, he tortures them,
and not only burns, but roasts, them to death; if his castle is
always wet with freshly shed blood -then not to return a benefit to
him is too small a thing! For whatever the tie that bound him
to me, it has been severed by his breach of the common bond of
humanity. {common_bond+} If he had
bestowed something upon me, and yet bore arms against my country, he
would have lost all claim upon me, and it would be considered a
crime to repay him with gratitude. If he does not assail my
country, but is the bane of his own, and, while he keeps aloof from
my own people, harrows and rends his own, nevertheless, even if such
depravity does not make him my personal enemy, it makes him hateful
to me, and regard for the duty that I owe to the whole human race
is, in my eyes, more primary and more pressing than the duty I owe
to a single man. {common_bond+}
<Ess3-503>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xx. 1-5
But,
although this be so -, although I am free to act as I please toward
him, from the moment when by violating all law he put himself beyond
the pale of the law, I shall think that I ought to observe
moderation, as follows. If my benefit to him is likely neither
to increase his powers to work general harm, nor to strengthen what
he already has, if, too, it shall be of such a character that it can
be returned to him without being disastrous to the state, then I
shall return it. I shall be willing to save the life of his
infant son - for what harm can this benefit do to any of those whom
he tortures with his cruelty? - but I shall not supply him with
money to maintain his bodyguard. If he desires marbles and raiments,
these trappings of his luxury will do nobody any harm; but I shall
not furnish him with soldiers and arms. If, as a great boon, he asks
for stage-players and prostitutes and things that will
soften {Paris+} his fierce nature, I shall gladly
present them. I would not send to him triremes and bronze-beaked
ships,/a but I should send pleasure- boats and yachts and the other
playthings of kings who indulge in sport on the sea. And if
his sanity should be despaired of, with the hand that returns a
benefit/b to him, I shall bestow one on all men; since for such
characters the only remedy is death, and, if a man will probably
never return to his senses, it is best for him to depart. But
so rare is such a degree of wickedness that it is always regarded as
a portent - as much so as the yawning of the earth and the bursting
forth of fires from the caverns of the sea. So let us leave
it, and talk of vices that we can detest without shuddering. As for the type of bad
man that I can find in any market- place, who is feared, but only by
individuals, <Ess3-505>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xx. 5-xxii. 1
I shall return to him the benefit that I
have received. It is not right that I should profit by his
wickedness; let me return what is not mine to its owner. What
difference does it make whether he is good or bad? But I would
sift out that matter most carefully if I were giving, not returning,
a benefit. This point calls up a story. A certain
Pythagorean once bought some white shoes/a from a cobbler, a fine
pair, without paying for them in cash. Some days later he
returned to the shop in order to make payment, and, after he had
been knocking for a long time at the closed door, someone appeared,
and said: "Why do you waste your time? The Cobbler you
are looking for passed away, and has been cremated; this is,
perhaps, a grief to us, who believe that we lose our friends for
ever, but not to you, who know that they will be reborn," jeering at
the Pythagorean./b But our philosopher, not unwillingly, carried his
three or four denarii back home, shaking them now and then in his
hand. Later, after blaming himself for the secret pleasure he
had had from not paying the money, and perceiving that he had
derived satisfaction from his trifling gain, he returned to the same
shop, saying to himself: "For you the man is alive, pay him
what you owe." Thereupon, he dropped the four coins into the shop,
thrusting them through the closed door by means of a crack in the
joining, and exacted punishment of himself for his unconscionable
greed in order that he might not form the habit of being in debt.
Try to find
someone to whom you can pay what you owe, and, if no one demands it,
do you dun yourself. It is no concern of yours whether the man
is good or bad; first pay, then accuse. You have forgotten how
<Ess3-507>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxii. 1-xxiii. 2
your several duties have been divided - for
him forgetfulness is enjoined, for you we have decreed
remembrance. Yet it is a mistake to suppose that, when we say
that the man who has given a benefit ought to forget, we would rob
him of all memory of his act, especially if it was a very honourable
one. We overstate some rules in order that in the end they may
reach their true value. When we say: "He must not
remember," we really mean: "He must not babble, nor
boast+, nor give offence." For some men in all gatherings tell
of a benefit that they have given; talk of it when they are sober,
make no secret of it when they are drunk, force it upon strangers,
confide it to friends. It is to quell this excessive and
reprehensible consciousness of it that we have said that the man who
gives must forget, and, by ordering something more than he is able
to accomplish, have commended to him silence. Whenever you lack
confidence in those to whom you are giving orders, you should demand
of them more than is necessary in order that they may perform all
that is necessary. The set purpose of all hyperbole is to
arrive at the truth by falsehood. And so when the poet said:
Whose whiteness shamed the snow,
their speed the winds,/a he stated what could not
possibly be true in order to give credence to all that could be
true. And the other who said:
Firmer than a rock, more
headlong than the stream,/b did not suppose that he
could convince anyone by this that any person was as immovable as a
rock. Hyperbole never expects to attain all that it <Ess3-509>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxiii. 2-xxv. 1
ventures, but asserts the incredible in
order to arrive at the credible. When we say: "Let him who
gives a benefit forget it," we mean: "Let him seem to have
forgotten it; let not his memory of it appear or obtrude." When we
say that we ought not to demand the repayment of a benefit, we do
not banish every demand for repayment; for bad men often need to be
dunned, even good men to be reminded. What, then? Am I
not to point out an opportunity to one who is not aware of it?
Am I not to reveal my own wants? Why should anyone have the
chance to deny or be sorry that he did not know of them?
Sometimes we may venture to remind, but modestly, with no air of
making a demand or of claiming a legal right. Socrates once said in
the hearing of his friends: "I would have bought a cloak, if I had
had the money." He asked from no one, he reminded all. Rivalry
sprang up as to who should be allowed to give it to him. Why
should there not have been? For how small a thing it was that
Socrates was receiving! But to have been the one from whom
Socrates received was a great thing. Could he have upbraided
them more gently? "I would have bought a cloak," he said, "if
I had had the money." After this, whoever made haste to give, gave
too late; he had already failed in duty to Socrates. Because
some men are harsh in demanding repayment, we forbid it, not in
order that the demand may never be made, but that it may be made
sparingly. Once
when Aristippus/a was enjoying the odour of a perfume, he
cried: "Curses upon these effeminate fellows who have cast
discredit on so nice a thing!" So, too, we should exclaim:
"Curses upon these un <Ess3-511>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxv. 1-xxvi. 2
conscionable and importunate magnifiers of
their benefits who have banished so nice a thing as the right of one
friend to remind another!" I, however, shall make use of this
privilege of friendship, and I shall ask the return of a benefit
from anyone from whom I would have asked a benefit, who will be
ready to accept as a second benefit the opportunity of returning the
first. Not even when complaining of him would I ever say
Needy I found him, a wretch, cast
up on the shore And, cool, the half of my
kingdom I made his store./a This is not to remind, but
to reproach; this is to make a benefit hateful, this is to give a
man either the right, or the pleasure, of being ungrateful. It would
be enough, and more than enough, to refresh his memory with the
gentle and friendly words:
If I to you by aught have
help or pleasure brought/b and he, in turn, would
say: "Brought me help? 'Needy you found me, a wretch, cast up
on the shore!'"
"But," you say, "if we gain nothing; if he dissembles if he forgets
- what ought I to do?" You now bring up the very pressing question,
which will fittingly complete our subject, of how we are to deal
with the ungrateful. I answer, deal calmly, gently,
magnanimously. Never let anyone's discourtesy, forgetfulness, and
ingratitude offend you so much that you will not, after all, be glad
that you gave; never let the injustice of it drive vou into saying
"I wish that I had not done it." You should find pleasure even
in the mischance of your benefit; the <Ess3-513>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxvi. 2-5
ingrate will always regret it if you do not
even now egret it! There is no reason why you should be
exasperated as if something strange had happened; you ought rather
to have been surprised if it had not happened. One balks at the
trouble, another at the expense, another at the danger, another is
deterred by false shame, since returning the benefit would be an
admission that he had received it, another by ignorance of his duty,
another by laziness, another by the engrossments of business.
See how greedy are men's desires and always asking for more!
You need not wonder that no one makes return in a world where no one
is satisfied. Who of men is of so firm and dependable a mind
that you can safely deposit your benefits with him? {motives_list+} One is crazed by lust,
another is the slave of his belly; another is wholly engrossed with
gain and considers, not the means, but the amount, of it; another
struggles with envy, another with blind ambition that drives him to
the sword. Consider, too, mental sluggishness and senility,
and opposed to them, the perpetual turmoil and commotion of the
restless heart. Consider, too, excessive self-esteem and
swollen pride in the things for which a man should be
despised. And what shall I say of the obstinate persistence in
wrongdoing, what of the fickleness that is always leaping from one
thing to another? Add to these the headlong rashness, the fear
that is never ready to give faithful counsel, and the thousand
errors in which we are entangled the audacity of the greatest of
cowards, the discord of the greatest of friends, and the universal
evil of trusting in everything that is most uncertain, and of
disdaining the possessions that once we had no hope <Ess3-515>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxvi. 5-xxviii. 1
of ever being able to attain. In the
company of the most restless passions do you hope to find that
calmest of qualities, good faith+? If a true picture of
our life should be flashed before your mind, you would think that
you were seeing the representation of a city that had just been
stormed, in which all regard for decency and right had been
abandoned and only force holds sway, as if the word had gone out to
cause universal confusion. Fire is not idle, the sword is not
idle; all crime is free from the law; not even religion, which has
protected its suppliants in the midst of a hostile invasion, affords
any check upon those rushing to seize plunder. This one strips
a private house, this one a public building, this one a sacred
place, this one a place profane; this one breaks down, this one
leaps over; this one, not content with a narrow path, overthrows the
very walls that block his way, and reaches his booty over ruins; one
ravages without murdering, another bears his spoils in a hand
stained with blood; everyone carries off something that belongs to
another. O! you
have too easily forgotten the common lot, if, in this greed of the
human race, you seek to find among these plunderers even one who
brings back! If you are indignant that men are ungrateful, be
indignant that they are sybaritic, indignant that they are greedy,
indignant that they are shameless, indignant that the sick are
unsightly, that the old are pale! This is, indeed, a heinous
vice, it is intolerable - one that sets men at variance, that rends
and destroys the harmony {social_glue+}
which props our human weakness, but it is so common {nobody's_perfect+} that not even he who
complains of it escapes it. Ask your secret soul whether you
have always <Ess3-517>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxviii. 1-xxix. 1
repaid gratitude to those to whom you owed
it, whether no one's kindness has ever been wasted on you, whether
the memory of all your benefits lives ever in you. You will
find that those you received as a boy slipped from your memory
before you were a youth, those that were bestowed in your early
manhood have not survived into old age. Some we have lost,
some we have thrown away, some have gradually slipped from our
sight, from some we have turned away our eyes. In order to
excuse your weakness, I might say that the memory is a very frail
vessel, and is not strong enough to hold a mass of things; it must
necessarily lose to the extent that it receives, and the newest
impressions crowd out the oldest. Thus it is that your nurse
has least influence over you because the passing years have left her
benefit in the long ago; thus it is that you have no longer any
veneration for your teacher; so it happens that now, when you are
occupied with your election to the consulship or your candidature
for the priesthood, you have lost all memory of the voter who gave
you the quaestorship. Perhaps, if you search carefully, you
will find in your own bosom the vice of which you complain. {Common_Humanity+} It is unfair for you to
be angry with a universal failing, foolish to be angry with your own
- you must pardon if you would win pardon. {judge_not+}
You will make a man better by bearing with him, certainly worse by
reproaching him. There is no reason why you should harden him
in effrontery; let him keep what little shame he has. Too loud
reproaches often hurry wavering probity to its fall. No man
shrinks from being what he appears to be; he loses his sense of
shame by being found out. "I have wasted my benefit," you
say. Can we <Ess3-519>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxix. 1-xxx. 2
ever say that we have wasted the things that
we have hallowed? But a benefit that has been well bestowed,
even if we have ill return for it, is one of the hallowed
things. He is not the kind of man we hoped he was; unlike him,
let us be the kind we have always been. Your loss did not
occur at the time of his ingratitude - it then simply became
evident. A man is not revealed as ungrateful without bringing
shame on us, since, in fact, to complain of the loss of a benefit is
proof that it was not well bestowed. As far as we can, we ought to
plead his case before our own bar: "Perhaps he was not able,
perhaps he was unaware, perhaps he will still do so." Some accounts
have been made good by a long-suffering and wise creditor who has
kept them alive and nursed them by waiting. We ought to do the
same; let us strengthen a weak sense of good faith. "I have
wasted my benefit," you say. You fool, you do not understand
when your loss took place! You wasted it, but at the time you
gave it; {no_strings+} the fact has only now been
revealed. Even in the case of those which seem to have been
wasted, forbearance is often most valuable; the cankers of the mind,
as of the body, must be handled tenderly. The string that
might have been untied by patience is often snapped by a violent
pull. What need is there of abuse? Of complaints? Of
reproaches? Why do you free him from obligation? Why do
you let him go? Even if he is ungrateful, he owes you nothing
after this. What sense is there in exasperating one upon whom
you have bestowed great favours, with the result that from being a
doubtful friend he will become an undoubted enemy, and will seek to
protect himself by defaming you, nor will gossip fail to <Ess3-521>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxx.2-xxxl. 4
say: "I do not know why he could not
put up with one to whom he owed so much; there is something at the
bottom of it"? Any man, even if he does not stain, asperses
the reputation of a superior by complaining of him; and no one is
content to trump up light accusations, since he seeks to win belief
by the very magnitude of his lie. How much better the
course that will preserve a semblance of friendship with him, and,
if he returns to his senses, even friendship! Persistent
goodness wins over bad men, and no one of them is so hard-hearted
and hostile to kindly treatment as not to love a good man even while
they wrong him, when even the fact that they can fail to pay with
impunity is made an additional source of indebtedness to
him. {forgive+} And so let your thoughts follow
this trend: "He has not repaid me with gratitude; what shall I
do? Do as the gods, those glorious authors of all things, do;
they begin to give benefits to him who knows them not, and persist
in giving them to those who are ungrateful. Some reproach them
with indifference to us, others with injustice; some/a place them
outside of their world, and abandon them to sloth and languor,
leaving them without light, without any task; others call the sun,
to whom we owe the division of our hours of work and rest, and our
escape from being plunged into darkness and the chaos of eternal
night, who by his course regulates the seasons, nourishes our
bodies, calls forth the crops, and ripens the fruits, merely a mass
of stone or a fortuitous collection of fiery particles - anything
rather than a god. Yet, none the less, like the best of
parents, who only smile at the spiteful words of their children, the
gods do not cease to heap their benefits upon those <Ess3-523>
ON BENEFITS, VII. xxxi. 4-xxxii. 1
who are doubtful about the source of
benefits, but distribute their blessings, among the nations and
peoples with unbroken uniformity. Possessing only the power of
doing good, they sprinkle the lands with timely rains, they stir the
seas with their blasts, they mark off the seasons by the course of
the stars, they modify the extremes of summer and winter by
interposing periods of milder temperature, and, ever gentle and
kindly, bear with the errors of our feeble spirits. {Nature+} Let us imitate them; let us give,
even if many of our gifts have been given in vain; none the less,
let us give to still others, nay, even to those at whose hands we
have suffered loss. The destruction of one house deters no one
from erecting another, and, when fire has swept away our household
gods, we lay new foundations while the ground is still hot, and over
and over we entrust new cities to the same spot that has swallowed
up others; so persistently does the mind foster fair hopes+.
Men would cease their operations on land and sea unless they had
been willing to renew the attempts that had failed. xxx"If a man is
ungrateful, he has done, not me, but himself, an injury; I had the
fruit of my benefit when I gave it. {give_freely+}
And the experience will make me, not slower to give, but more
careful in giving; what I have lost in the case of one man, I shall
recover from others. But even to him I shall give a second
benefit, and, even as a good farmer overcomes the sterility of his
ground by care and cultivation, I shall be victor; my benefit is
lost to me, he is lost to mankind. It is no proof of a fine
spirit to give a benefit and lose it; the proof of a fine spirit is
to lose and still to give!" <Ess3-525>
. |